Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
By GE Morton
#350142
Terrapin Station wrote: February 20th, 2020, 9:57 am
So you ask 50 people, and at least a few of them say "It is not raining."

Is that no longer an objective proposition then?
The proposition is objective if its truth conditions are public. Whether or not it is raining is a publicly observable state of affairs, ascertainable by looking out a window or stepping outside. If some of your observers step out, come in dripping wet and deny it is raining they are delusional or lying.
By GE Morton
#350143
Terrapin Station wrote: February 20th, 2020, 10:46 am
"Objective proposition" is a bad term for that, though, for a number of reasons. First, usually the "adjective noun" form suggests that the adjective is telling us a property of the noun as an existent. For example, "red ball," "tall man," "reticulated python." In those cases, "red," "tall," and "reticulated" are properties that the noun they modify "possesses." But with "objective proposition," the proposition itself isn't an object or objective. The way you and others are attempting to use this term is akin to saying, "Red book" when the book itself is in no way red, but is rather a book about the color red. If you were to say, "That's a red book" to someone, you shouldn't be surprised when they say, "Red? What are you talking about. My copy of the book has no red. The cover is black with white lettering. The pages are white with black ink."

Or once again, this is an example of use/mention confusion.
No, it isn't. For "objective proposition" the adjective does not denote a natural or perceptible property. It is an imputed property; a pseudo-property imputed to things to mark some external fact about them. The language is rife with such properties, e.g., "Alfie is a married man," "Bruno is a doctor," "Chauncey is the lead actor in Othello", the "Dead Sea Scrolls," etc. "Tall man" is a perceptible property; "married man" is an imputed property. You confirm perceptible properties by examining the subject; to confirm imputed properties you must verify some fact beyond the subject. You can't confirm that the scroll before you came from the Dead Sea by examining the scroll. You need some information as to where it was found.
By Peter Holmes
#350145
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 1:48 pm
Peter Holmes wrote: February 20th, 2020, 7:19 am
Couldn't agree more. And I wonder why this glaringly obvious fact is so hard for many people to grasp.
I agree too. But what is "good" is a question for axiology, not morality.
I find your exclusive demarcation of axiology puzzling. Here's a definition of axiology:

'Axiology (from Greek ἀξία, axia, "value, worth"; and -λογία, -logia) is the philosophical study of value. It is either the collective term for ethics and aesthetics[1], philosophical fields that depend crucially on notions of worth, or the foundation for these fields, and thus similar to value theory and meta-ethics. The term was first used by Paul Lapie, in 1902,[2][3] and Eduard von Hartmann, in 1908.[4][5]

Axiology studies mainly two kinds of values: ethics and aesthetics. Ethics investigates the concepts of "right" and "good" in individual and social conduct. Aesthetics studies the concepts of "beauty" and "harmony." Formal axiology, the attempt to lay out principles regarding value with mathematical rigor, is exemplified by Robert S. Hartman's science of value.'

Can you explain, in simple terms, why you think ethics and morality have nothing to do with questions about value - what people value?
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350148
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 2:01 pm I answered that question many posts back. The association between a word and a thing --- the thing that is its meaning --- is learned
Non-mentally?

Or otherwise, how does it wind up transferring to non-mental things? So that the association occurs non-mentally?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350149
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 2:52 pm No, it isn't. For "objective proposition" the adjective does not denote a natural or perceptible property. It is an imputed property; a pseudo-property imputed to things to mark some external fact about them. The language is rife with such properties, e.g., "Alfie is a married man," "Bruno is a doctor," "Chauncey is the lead actor in Othello", the "Dead Sea Scrolls," etc. "Tall man" is a perceptible property; "married man" is an imputed property. You confirm perceptible properties by examining the subject; to confirm imputed properties you must verify some fact beyond the subject. You can't confirm that the scroll before you came from the Dead Sea by examining the scroll. You need some information as to where it was found.
In all of the examples you're giving, the imputed properties are still properties of the object in question. The man is married. That's a property he has. The scrolls are from the Dead Sea. That's a property they have.

In the case of "objective proposition," "objective" is not a property the proposition itself has. It's a property, if we're realists, of what the proposition is about.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350150
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 2:27 pm If some of your observers step out, come in dripping wet and deny it is raining they are delusional or lying.
And "They are delusional or lying" isn't a judgment you're making?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350152
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 2:14 pm Whether they agree or not is irrelevant. What makes the proposition objective is the mere fact that they are all basing their verdicts on examination of the rock. That they can't agree merely means they need to examine it more carefully. A proposition is objective if its truth conditions are public, which they are in this case. There is no requirement that all observers agree. A subjective proposition, in contrast, would be, "This rock is beautiful."
"They make their judgment by examining something objective" is different than saying "verifiable by a suitably situated observer."

After all, if no one ever verifies the claim in question, then in what way does it make sense to say that it's verifiable?

Re "a proposition is 'objective' just in case judgments are made about it by examining something extramental" is going to have the problem of "something extramental in whose judgment?" As of course ontological idealists are not going to agree that anyone is ever examining anything extramental.

You're saying that whether they're "suitably situated" isn't a judgment. Well, what decides whether the people in question are "suitably situated" then? Simply whether they verify the proposition? "For any proposition, P, you're suitably situated if you verify it, otherwise you're not suitably situated." That can't be right, can it?
A person is suitably situated if he is in a position to examine the rock --- to inspect it, run tests on it, etc. You're being obtuse, TP.
Per the view of someone claiming the rock to be objective?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350153
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 2:27 pm
What I was most interested in your addressing was something you completely ignored (though no surprise that you just ignored it:)

Let's say that we have "Paris is the capital of France" written or in sound (like a recording) or something.

Now, what exactly happens for the marks on the paper or the sound to have "true" or "false" assigned to it relative to non-mental things in the world.

Remember, if you say anything that involves people doing things where they need to be mentally active--making observations, making decisions, making judgments, etc. you're going to get a buzzer, because you're claiming that truth ascriptions have NOTHING to do with ANYTHING in people's heads.

So we've got the marks on paper or a computer screen or a sound recording of "Paris is the capital of France." What happens next so that we have a truth-value ascription on your view?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By GE Morton
#350168
Peter Holmes wrote: February 20th, 2020, 3:01 pm
I find your exclusive demarcation of axiology puzzling. Here's a definition of axiology:

'Axiology (from Greek ἀξία, axia, "value, worth"; and -λογία, -logia) is the philosophical study of value. It is either the collective term for ethics and aesthetics[1], philosophical fields that depend crucially on notions of worth, or the foundation for these fields, and thus similar to value theory and meta-ethics. The term was first used by Paul Lapie, in 1902,[2][3] and Eduard von Hartmann, in 1908.[4][5]

Axiology studies mainly two kinds of values: ethics and aesthetics. Ethics investigates the concepts of "right" and "good" in individual and social conduct. Aesthetics studies the concepts of "beauty" and "harmony." Formal axiology, the attempt to lay out principles regarding value with mathematical rigor, is exemplified by Robert S. Hartman's science of value.'
Your source is embracing the confounding of values and morality that has plagued the history of philosophy. What is valuable ("good") and what is moral are two entirely different questions. Morality is commonly understood to be concerned with behavior, with how people treat one another, with the rightness or wrongness of acts by moral agents. It is not concerned with whether chocolate ice cream is better than vanilla, or the life of a scholar is "better" than the life of a farmer, or whether extramarital sex is good or bad. Values --- what is deemed good or bad --- are intrinsically subjective. As long as such questions are intermingled with questions about the rightness or wrongness of actions morality will indeed remain subjective.

To be sure, we also apply "good" and "bad" to behaviors. But usually we so deem them because we judge those actions (morally) right or wrong. Whether an act is "bad" is a subjective judgment on our part (we're saying we don't like it). But whether it is wrong can be objective.
Can you explain, in simple terms, why you think ethics and morality have nothing to do with questions about value - what people value?
Morality has something to do with values --- it assumes that people value things, things that enhance their welfare, give them satisfaction, add meaning to their lives. But it does not assume or promote any particular values, all of which are idiosyncratic and relative to particular agents. What is morally relevant is the fact that people value things, not what they value. "Moral values" is an oxymoron.
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350169
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 8:02 pm
Your source is embracing the confounding of values and morality that has plagued the history of philosophy. What is valuable ("good") and what is moral are two entirely different questions. Morality is commonly understood to be concerned with behavior, with how people treat one another, with the rightness or wrongness of acts by moral agents. It is not concerned with whether chocolate ice cream is better than vanilla, or the life of a scholar is "better" than the life of a farmer, or whether extramarital sex is good or bad. Values --- what is deemed good or bad --- are intrinsically subjective. As long as such questions are intermingled with questions about the rightness or wrongness of actions morality will indeed remain subjective.
Oy vey. What you wrote above is confused.

When we're talking about good in a moral context we're not talking about gastronomy, aesthetics, etc.

Good in a moral context is the same thing as "right conduct."
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Peter Holmes
#350185
GE Morton wrote: February 20th, 2020, 8:02 pm
Peter Holmes wrote: February 20th, 2020, 3:01 pm
I find your exclusive demarcation of axiology puzzling. Here's a definition of axiology:

'Axiology (from Greek ἀξία, axia, "value, worth"; and -λογία, -logia) is the philosophical study of value. It is either the collective term for ethics and aesthetics[1], philosophical fields that depend crucially on notions of worth, or the foundation for these fields, and thus similar to value theory and meta-ethics. The term was first used by Paul Lapie, in 1902,[2][3] and Eduard von Hartmann, in 1908.[4][5]

Axiology studies mainly two kinds of values: ethics and aesthetics. Ethics investigates the concepts of "right" and "good" in individual and social conduct. Aesthetics studies the concepts of "beauty" and "harmony." Formal axiology, the attempt to lay out principles regarding value with mathematical rigor, is exemplified by Robert S. Hartman's science of value.'
Your source is embracing the confounding of values and morality that has plagued the history of philosophy. What is valuable ("good") and what is moral are two entirely different questions. Morality is commonly understood to be concerned with behavior, with how people treat one another, with the rightness or wrongness of acts by moral agents. It is not concerned with whether chocolate ice cream is better than vanilla, or the life of a scholar is "better" than the life of a farmer, or whether extramarital sex is good or bad. Values --- what is deemed good or bad --- are intrinsically subjective. As long as such questions are intermingled with questions about the rightness or wrongness of actions morality will indeed remain subjective.

To be sure, we also apply "good" and "bad" to behaviors. But usually we so deem them because we judge those actions (morally) right or wrong. Whether an act is "bad" is a subjective judgment on our part (we're saying we don't like it). But whether it is wrong can be objective.
Can you explain, in simple terms, why you think ethics and morality have nothing to do with questions about value - what people value?
Morality has something to do with values --- it assumes that people value things, things that enhance their welfare, give them satisfaction, add meaning to their lives. But it does not assume or promote any particular values, all of which are idiosyncratic and relative to particular agents. What is morally relevant is the fact that people value things, not what they value. "Moral values" is an oxymoron.
I'm sorry, but I find this explanation unconvincing. We make value-judgements about different things, for sure. But they remain value-judgements, and are therefore subjective - matters of opinion or belief. And because of this, there's no substantial difference between a moral value-judgement and, say, an aesthetic one; 'this action is morally good' and 'this painting is beautiful' are equally subjective, and they equally lack truth-value, because moral goodness and aesthetic beauty aren't objective properties of features of reality. Rather, we use these signs to express opinions about things.

Your analysis is contradictory: 'Morality has something to do with values', but '"Moral values" is an oxymoron'. Of course, the word 'morality' is morally neutral - who ever thought it wasn't? But what could moral discourse consist of if it isn't talk about moral rightness and wrongness, and the value-judgements that inform such talk?
By Steve3007
#350187
Steve3007 wrote:If somebody on the News says "The Whitehouse has released a statement", we don't all say "Huh?!? How can a house, whatever its colour, release a statement?". We understand what that shorthand means.
A more obscure one, in Britain, is to say "Number 10 has released a statement".

"How can an abstract concept like a number think or speak, let alone release a statement?" I say for sh!ts and giggles. A lot of linguistic humour seems to be based on deliberately taking English language constructs too literally. So I guess in philosophy comedy clubs the stand-up might say:

"I heard somebody making an 'objective proposition' the other day. Huh? How can a mental construct like a proposition be reified into an object? What's that about?"

I'm sure that would bring the house down.
By Peter Holmes
#350192
Steve3007 wrote: February 21st, 2020, 7:31 am
Steve3007 wrote:If somebody on the News says "The Whitehouse has released a statement", we don't all say "Huh?!? How can a house, whatever its colour, release a statement?". We understand what that shorthand means.
A more obscure one, in Britain, is to say "Number 10 has released a statement".

"How can an abstract concept like a number think or speak, let alone release a statement?" I say for sh!ts and giggles. A lot of linguistic humour seems to be based on deliberately taking English language constructs too literally. So I guess in philosophy comedy clubs the stand-up might say:

"I heard somebody making an 'objective proposition' the other day. Huh? How can a mental construct like a proposition be reified into an object? What's that about?"

I'm sure that would bring the house down.
Can you spell out what you mean? Are you saying the expression 'objective proposition' contains a transferred epithet? And are you making a point about the supposed objectivity of morality - that moral opinions can be independent from opinion?
  • 1
  • 23
  • 24
  • 25
  • 26
  • 27
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


🤣🤣🤣 You are so brainwashed that you can'[…]

This topic is about the February 2025 Philosophy […]

I agree. But why should we consider liberta[…]

Quite true. We are not in a place at many occasion[…]