Idealism(s)
Posted: March 29th, 2022, 11:44 am
Reposted from here: viewtopic.php?p=407975#p407975
* subjective idealism
* objective idealism
* absolute idealism
* transcendental idealism
* …?
QUOTE>
"Types of philosophical idealism:
Berkeley’s idealism is called subjective idealism, because he reduced reality to spirits (his name for subjects) and to the ideas entertained by spirits. In Berkeley’s philosophy the apparent objectivity of the world outside the self was accommodated to his subjectivism by claiming that its objects are ideas in the mind of God. The foundation for a series of more-objective idealisms was laid by the 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant, whose epochal work Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1781; 2nd ed. 1787; Critique of Pure Reason) presented a formalistic or transcendental idealism, so named because Kant thought that the human self, or “transcendental ego,” constructs knowledge out of sense impressions, upon which are imposed certain universal concepts that he called categories. Three systems constructed in Germany in the early 19th century by, respectively, the moral idealist Johann Gottlieb Fichte, the aesthetic idealist Friedrich Schelling, and Hegel, all on a foundation laid by Kant, are referred to as objective idealism, in contrast to Berkeley’s subjective idealism. The designations, however, are not consistent, and when the contrast with Berkeley is not at issue, Fichte himself is often called a subjective idealist, inasmuch as he exalted the subject above the object, employing the term Ego to mean God in the two memorable propositions: “The Ego posits itself” and “The Ego posits the non-Ego (or nature).” In contrast to the subjective idealism of Fichte, Schelling’s is called an objective idealism, and Hegel’s is called an absolute idealism.
All those terms form backgrounds for modern Western idealisms, most of which are based either on Kant’s transcendental idealism or on those of Fichte, Schelling, or Hegel. Exceptions are those based on other great idealists of the past—Plato, Plotinus, Spinoza, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and others. ……"
Types of Philosophical Idealism: https://www.britannica.com/topic/ideali ... l-idealism
<QUOTE
QUOTE>
"Idealism is difficult to define precisely. In this it is similar to other general and rival approaches to metaphysics, including materialism and dualism. Roughly speaking, we may say that idealists endorse the priority of the mental. This definition needs some unpacking and different versions of idealism will unpack it differently. As we will see, different idealistic theories attribute very different sorts of priority to the mental.
George Berkeley’s view that minds and their ideas are all the beings there are is the most famous version of idealism. According to Berkeley, minds enjoy ontological priority: minds alone are fundamental and everything else depends on them. Berkeley particularly emphasizes the ontological priority of minds over bodies. However, there are many other versions of idealism. Leibniz, Kant, Hegel, and Bradley, for instance, each espoused a different version.
While many of these philosophical views are plausibly interpreted as attributing some kind of ontological priority to minds over bodies, they also often include other idealistic theses. For instance, Kantian transcendental idealism attributes a distinctive kind of explanatory priority to the mental: Kant argues that the structure of the understanding explains the structure of the empirical world. Idealism, in one or another of these versions, was the dominant philosophical view in Western philosophy throughout the nineteenth century.
But then idealism was given up. In the contemporary metaphysical debate about the contents of concrete reality, the two opposing camps are materialism and dualism. Materialism takes the world to be fundamentally material (or physical). Dualism takes a part of the world to be fundamentally mental and another part to be fundamentally material. In each case, the assumption is usually that the world or a part of it cannot at once be fundamentally mental and fundamentally material. These views then reject Berkeley’s claim of the ontological priority of the mental. Typically, they also reject other idealistic claims, holding that the mental is either posterior to or coordinate with the physical in any metaphysically interesting priority ordering."
(Goldschmidt, Tyron, and Kenneth L. Pearce. Introduction to Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics, edited by Tyron Goldschmidt and Kenneth L. Pearce, ix-xii. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017. p. ix)
<QUOTE
SteveKlinko wrote: ↑March 29th, 2022, 7:52 amWhat makes understanding idealism complicated is that there is more than one type of it:Belindi wrote: ↑March 28th, 2022, 5:53 pm A usual way to come to understand idealism is to start with Bishop George Berkeley' s version of idealism. "To be is to be perceived".And thank you for the answers. I have struggled to understand Idealism for decades, but can never make sense out of it. I suppose Berkeley was the first to talk about it. Never understood him. Don't get how Physical/Material reality does not exist.
* subjective idealism
* objective idealism
* absolute idealism
* transcendental idealism
* …?
QUOTE>
"Types of philosophical idealism:
Berkeley’s idealism is called subjective idealism, because he reduced reality to spirits (his name for subjects) and to the ideas entertained by spirits. In Berkeley’s philosophy the apparent objectivity of the world outside the self was accommodated to his subjectivism by claiming that its objects are ideas in the mind of God. The foundation for a series of more-objective idealisms was laid by the 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant, whose epochal work Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1781; 2nd ed. 1787; Critique of Pure Reason) presented a formalistic or transcendental idealism, so named because Kant thought that the human self, or “transcendental ego,” constructs knowledge out of sense impressions, upon which are imposed certain universal concepts that he called categories. Three systems constructed in Germany in the early 19th century by, respectively, the moral idealist Johann Gottlieb Fichte, the aesthetic idealist Friedrich Schelling, and Hegel, all on a foundation laid by Kant, are referred to as objective idealism, in contrast to Berkeley’s subjective idealism. The designations, however, are not consistent, and when the contrast with Berkeley is not at issue, Fichte himself is often called a subjective idealist, inasmuch as he exalted the subject above the object, employing the term Ego to mean God in the two memorable propositions: “The Ego posits itself” and “The Ego posits the non-Ego (or nature).” In contrast to the subjective idealism of Fichte, Schelling’s is called an objective idealism, and Hegel’s is called an absolute idealism.
All those terms form backgrounds for modern Western idealisms, most of which are based either on Kant’s transcendental idealism or on those of Fichte, Schelling, or Hegel. Exceptions are those based on other great idealists of the past—Plato, Plotinus, Spinoza, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and others. ……"
Types of Philosophical Idealism: https://www.britannica.com/topic/ideali ... l-idealism
<QUOTE
QUOTE>
"Idealism is difficult to define precisely. In this it is similar to other general and rival approaches to metaphysics, including materialism and dualism. Roughly speaking, we may say that idealists endorse the priority of the mental. This definition needs some unpacking and different versions of idealism will unpack it differently. As we will see, different idealistic theories attribute very different sorts of priority to the mental.
George Berkeley’s view that minds and their ideas are all the beings there are is the most famous version of idealism. According to Berkeley, minds enjoy ontological priority: minds alone are fundamental and everything else depends on them. Berkeley particularly emphasizes the ontological priority of minds over bodies. However, there are many other versions of idealism. Leibniz, Kant, Hegel, and Bradley, for instance, each espoused a different version.
While many of these philosophical views are plausibly interpreted as attributing some kind of ontological priority to minds over bodies, they also often include other idealistic theses. For instance, Kantian transcendental idealism attributes a distinctive kind of explanatory priority to the mental: Kant argues that the structure of the understanding explains the structure of the empirical world. Idealism, in one or another of these versions, was the dominant philosophical view in Western philosophy throughout the nineteenth century.
But then idealism was given up. In the contemporary metaphysical debate about the contents of concrete reality, the two opposing camps are materialism and dualism. Materialism takes the world to be fundamentally material (or physical). Dualism takes a part of the world to be fundamentally mental and another part to be fundamentally material. In each case, the assumption is usually that the world or a part of it cannot at once be fundamentally mental and fundamentally material. These views then reject Berkeley’s claim of the ontological priority of the mental. Typically, they also reject other idealistic claims, holding that the mental is either posterior to or coordinate with the physical in any metaphysically interesting priority ordering."
(Goldschmidt, Tyron, and Kenneth L. Pearce. Introduction to Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics, edited by Tyron Goldschmidt and Kenneth L. Pearce, ix-xii. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017. p. ix)
<QUOTE