Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
#351809
GE Morton wrote: March 4th, 2020, 11:47 pm

You have missed the entire thrust of my argument.
It wasn't a reply to you. But okay, maybe that's your argument at any rate.
There is no uniquely or distinctly "moral sense" of "should," or "ought."

Sure there is and I just explained it.

Morally, we're not talking about a condition that has to be met for achieving something, but there's a colloquial way of using "should" for that.

It's a precondition of going up to the roof with a ladder that we have a ladder. So it's not uncommon to say in that situation, "You should have a ladder to go up to the roof with a ladder."

But that's not the gist of a moral normative. There's nothing moral about the "should" there. It's simply an alternate way of noting a precondition for achieving something.

Moral normatives are rather focused on "right conduct," in a value sense of being an admirable, virtuous way to behave, where there are available options where other options would be "wrong conduct."

That's why it's not considered moral to pull the trigger of a gun and shoot someone in the head nonconsensually even though if you have a goal of shooting someone in the head with a gun, you "should" pull the trigger--that's a precondition for shooting someone in the head with a gun.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#351811
GE Morton wrote: March 4th, 2020, 11:47 pm
It is the very same sense of "should." The only difference is that the goal sought is not a moral one.
The whole aim of objective morality is that people want the morality part to be objective. Hence why we use the phrase "objective morality," where we have the adjective "objective" modifying the noun, "morality."

You're talking about objective preconditions for achieving something, rather, and you're misleadingly calling that "morality." If some goals "are not moral goals," then what is determining that? Surely nothing objective. Which means there's nothing objective about morality per se.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Belindi
#351813
GEMorton wrote:
Also, attempts to promote or encourage or instill any attitude, personality trait, or emotional response pattern are usually quixotic, futile.
As matter of fact powerful men constantly try to change , encourage, or indoctrinate attitudes throughout recorded history and here, there, and now.

Agape is widely associated with order and civilisation.Why would you want to remain cynical ? Cynicism which must be associated with intransigence will accomplish nothing.
#351817
Re preconditions, by the way, we should probably make a distinction between logical preconditions and contingent, "practical" preconditions.

It's a logical precondition that if you want to go up to the roof with a ladder, you need a ladder. It's a contingent, practical precondition that if you want to shoot someone in the head with a gun, you need to pull the trigger--given that contingently, you don't have a gun where you could activate it by pushing a button instead, or saying "shoot" instead, etc.

Also, we should make a distinction between necessary preconditions and sufficient preconditions. Most of the time with most morality talk, we're going to be suggesting sufficient preconditions to achieve some goal, not necessary preconditions, and it's often going to be a (subjective) judgment as to whether particular actions are either necessary or sufficient preconditions. Given the moral goals people usually have, it's rarely clear that there are necessary preconditions in the vein of "if you want to go up to the roof with a ladder, you need a ladder," or even, "if you want to murder someone, then you need a good weapon and/or some basic physiological knowledge/combat skills."
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#351818
Terrapin Station wrote: March 5th, 2020, 5:38 am
GE Morton wrote: March 4th, 2020, 11:47 pm
It is the very same sense of "should." The only difference is that the goal sought is not a moral one.
The whole aim of objective morality is that people want the morality part to be objective. Hence why we use the phrase "objective morality," where we have the adjective "objective" modifying the noun, "morality."

You're talking about objective preconditions for achieving something, rather, and you're misleadingly calling that "morality." If some goals "are not moral goals," then what is determining that? Surely nothing objective. Which means there's nothing objective about morality per se.
I think this discussion of the ways we use modals 'should', and so on, may be at the heart of what's wrong with GEM's argument. But I'll post separately about it. Sorry to butt in.
By Steve3007
#351821
Peter Holmes wrote:
Steve3007 wrote:I disagree that it's subjective all the way down. I think the question of whether going to school results in a good education is not an entirely subjective one. That's not saying it's not debatable. But it's not entirely subjective in the sense that, say, the statement "school is nice" is subjective.
That isn't the point. It may be that going to results in a good education. That may be an emprically verifiable fact. (It isn't, but never mind.)

But wanting to go to school, and wanting a good education, are both preferences, which are therefore subjective.
I disagree. I think that if they were merely tastes, with no underlying reason to them other than that they feel good, then you could say they were entirely subjective. But most preferences are not like that. People tend to present justifications for them in the form of emprical propositions. They make arguments. As I was saying, it's only when we follow those justifications until we reach something that can't be so justified that we find something that can be characterised as a personal taste. At that point, we could perhaps appeal to our evolved nature. So, in the example I gave, the line of analysis ended with:

"I want you to be happy."

Why do parents want their children to be happy? We could then bring in a discussion about such things as "selfish genes". We could thereby make an argument that our morality, and our moral choices, are determined by our biological nature.

An example you used in the OP was this:
Peter Holmes wrote:An objection to moral subjectivism is that, if moral values and judgements are matters of opinion, we can't know if they're correct. For example, we can't know if slavery is right or wrong, and can't therefore morally condemn those who think slavery is justifiable. That's just their opinion, and we can't say which opinion is correct or true.
If you were trying to present a case for slavery being wrong, perhaps to a slave owner, what kinds of things might you say? Would you simply say that slavery is not to your personal taste? Would you assert that there is some absolute moral law, perhaps derived from a religious edicts, that slavery is wrong?

In general, I think the way people try to present these cases is to use a process similar to the one I illustrated. They propose objective causal chains linking goals to deeper goals in the hope of finding common ground.
By Belindi
#351822
Objective morality is the same as morality that is necessarily so. 'Objective' means 'necessary'.

This must be the case because if an empirical fact is necessarily so it must be an objectively true fact. and vice versa. There is only one criterion for the truth of that claim and that criterion is order itself. If this is an ordered world and not a random one then all events must be caused events. Events with a moral attribute e.g. judicial hangings are compounded of civilised societies ' need for civil order, and the several causes of the punishable crime. All that causes any event with a moral attribute can be explained by reference to the orderliness of nature.
True, we constantly try to seek better solutions for the control of crimes and the promotion of happiness and our searching is also natural.

Some people think a supernatural being is the instigator of order. I think nature itself is sufficient to explain order.
By Steve3007
#351823
viewtopic.php?p=351680#p351680
Belindi wrote:As in "If you want to promote happiness and lessen pain then you should promote agape."

This juncture brings us to the question of utilitarianism as a candidate for objective morality.
If we're looking for an objective root to morality I don't think those various candidates for moral axioms that have been proposed over the years do the job because, being axioms, they're simply asserted without a proposed objectively verifiable justification. I think the only way to think of morality as objective (assuming we're not proposing the existence of a God) is to root the prescriptions in description. That is, to make observations about the evolved nature of human beings and extrapolate from those to observations of human behaviour and human desires.
#351825
Steve3007 wrote: March 5th, 2020, 6:58 am
Peter Holmes wrote:That isn't the point. It may be that going to results in a good education. That may be an emprically verifiable fact. (It isn't, but never mind.)

But wanting to go to school, and wanting a good education, are both preferences, which are therefore subjective.
I disagree. I think that if they were merely tastes, with no underlying reason to them other than that they feel good, then you could say they were entirely subjective. But most preferences are not like that. People tend to present justifications for them in the form of emprical propositions. They make arguments. As I was saying, it's only when we follow those justifications until we reach something that can't be so justified that we find something that can be characterised as a personal taste. At that point, we could perhaps appeal to our evolved nature. So, in the example I gave, the line of analysis ended with:

"I want you to be happy."

Why do parents want their children to be happy? We could then bring in a discussion about such things as "selfish genes". We could thereby make an argument that our morality, and our moral choices, are determined by our biological nature.

An example you used in the OP was this:
Peter Holmes wrote:An objection to moral subjectivism is that, if moral values and judgements are matters of opinion, we can't know if they're correct. For example, we can't know if slavery is right or wrong, and can't therefore morally condemn those who think slavery is justifiable. That's just their opinion, and we can't say which opinion is correct or true.
If you were trying to present a case for slavery being wrong, perhaps to a slave owner, what kinds of things might you say? Would you simply say that slavery is not to your personal taste? Would you assert that there is some absolute moral law, perhaps derived from a religious edicts, that slavery is wrong?

In general, I think the way people try to present these cases is to use a process similar to the one I illustrated. They propose objective causal chains linking goals to deeper goals in the hope of finding common ground.
When we say that something is a "taste" --that it's simply something the person likes or dislikes, yays or boos, we're not saying that there isn't a biological reason for it--obviously there is, because mental phenomena in general are biological phenomena, and there's going to be a biological reason for biological phenomena.

And obviously people think about, rationalize this stuff beyond just having a like or dislike where they don't relate that to anything else they feel or think. And obviously a big part of interacting with others about this stuff is trying to persuade others with respect to our preferences, often where we appeal to what we know about their preferences, their dispositions.

None of that makes any of this anything other than ways that people feel about things.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#351826
Steve3007 wrote: March 5th, 2020, 7:13 am
Belindi wrote:Objective morality is the same as morality that is necessarily so. 'Objective' means 'necessary'....
I essentially agree with what I take to be your point.
??? I didn't see that until you quoted it, but it's very unusual to say that objective things can't be contingent.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#351831
I think TS has found the real issue.

Moral objectivists claim that the assertion 'If we want goal Y, then we should do X' can be objective - which GEM defines as 'having public truth conditions' - if goal Y is what they call a moral goal. And this is by analogy with other assertions where Y is non-moral. To adapt TS's example -

If we want to get to the roof, then we [must/should/can/could] use a ladder.

Here, only 'can' and 'could' make the assertion true, because we can or could use a cherry-picker instead of a ladder. The choice of modal is critical for the truth-value of the assertion. With 'can' and 'could', the assertion is objective and has a truth-value. Modals 'must' and 'should' would have different functions here. And, given no other information, their use would render this assertion subjective, because it would then express an opinion, rather than a fact.

But notice the nature of the goal: 'to climb to the roof'. Like all terms, this has no truth-value, and it can't be objective or subjective, because only assertions can be one of those. And this is true of any object term in the conditional antecedent (the 'if' bit). For example: If we want chocolate, then... In other words, it isn't the object - goal Y - that confers objectivity and truth-value on the assertion. Instead, it's the claim being made by means of the modal - must/should/can/could - in the consequent (the 'then' bit).

(Of course, getting to the roof is something we can do, and something about which we can make objective factual assertions with truth-value. But that isn't the point here.)

To nail this: we can't use an assertion of any kind, moral or not, as the object in a conditional antecedent: If we want [chocolate is nice], then...; If we want [slavery is morally wrong], then...; If we want [our goal is world peace], then... The object - goal Y - has to be a term, and can't be an assertion. So goal Y in this kind of conditional premise can't be objective. Objectivity can come only from the claim made in the consequent.

Before pursuing this, does anyone have any thoughts about this analysis? And I need a lie down anyway.

(I'll come to 'If our goal is world peace, then...' - which is a different structure - later.)
#351835
The most ridiculous thing about this is that General Electric Morton claimed that we can have objective morality via there being things that are objectively required to meet some goal, but then he turns around and says that some goals wouldn't be moral, making obvious that the "moral" part of "objective morality" isn't objective at all in his view.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#351845
Terrapin Station wrote: March 5th, 2020, 7:48 am The most ridiculous thing about this is that General Electric Morton claimed that we can have objective morality via there being things that are objectively required to meet some goal, but then he turns around and says that some goals wouldn't be moral, making obvious that the "moral" part of "objective morality" isn't objective at all in his view.
Agreed. And that's a neat way of putting it. I'm laboriously trying to unpack the mistake, which may be a waste of time. If we're bewitched by the way we say things, maybe we can't reason away the problem.
User avatar
By chewybrian
#351854
Belindi wrote: March 5th, 2020, 7:07 am Objective morality is the same as morality that is necessarily so. 'Objective' means 'necessary'.

This must be the case because if an empirical fact is necessarily so it must be an objectively true fact. and vice versa.
So, if I am wearing a blue shirt, then it was 'necessary' that I put on a blue shirt today?
Belindi wrote: March 5th, 2020, 7:07 am There is only one criterion for the truth of that claim and that criterion is order itself. If this is an ordered world and not a random one then all events must be caused events.
What makes you say the world is ordered and not random? You could get hit by a meteor in your sleep tonight, or zapped by lightning, or struck with cancer, or eaten by a bear. Nature only rewards effort and common sense on a grand scale, and only some of the time. There is no order for the individual, and only intermittent order for the community. Most order I find in the world is imposed by people, and only acknowledged some of the time by some of them.
Belindi wrote: March 5th, 2020, 7:07 am All that causes any event with a moral attribute can be explained by reference to the orderliness of nature.
True, we constantly try to seek better solutions for the control of crimes and the promotion of happiness and our searching is also natural.

Some people think a supernatural being is the instigator of order. I think nature itself is sufficient to explain order.
Can you explain this a bit or give an example of how this works, step by step? If you were raped and murdered on your way home tonight, the order of nature would sufficiently explain the morality of the situation for you? Across town, someone else is feeding the homeless, and this is also fully explained by the order of nature, and has nothing to do with choice? It seems like you are claiming to understand morality while also claiming it does not, can not exist.
Favorite Philosopher: Epictetus Location: Florida man
  • 1
  • 45
  • 46
  • 47
  • 48
  • 49
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


🤣🤣🤣 You are so brainwashed that you can'[…]

This topic is about the February 2025 Philosophy […]

I agree. But why should we consider liberta[…]

Quite true. We are not in a place at many occasion[…]