Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#351155
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 1:35 pm The definitions state the accepted, understood meanings.
Definitions are the text or sound strings that we correlate with meanings. Meanings consist of the mental act of making associations where something like a text string implies or suggests an association with something else. That association doesn't occur anywhere but in minds. So no, it doesn't make ontological sense to say that definitions are meanings.
If someone attaches some different meaning to a common word he will have a hard time communicating.
We haven't the faintest idea what meaning anyone else is associating with terms, sounds, gestures, etc. That doesn't matter. We go by observables instead.

People can give very idiosyncratic definitions of terms. That's no barrier to communicating as long as they have the capability of understanding and remembering that someone else is using a term in a different way. For example, I can understand and remember the ways that you use terms differently than I do. So no communication problem on my end.
That amounts to learning a new language. But if someone is creating a new language by assigning new meanings to words with existing, universally understood meanings I'd assume he has some sophistic purpose in mind, and wouldn't bother.
Basically, "I'm not really interested enough in other people to bother with such things" and/or "I'm too lazy/intellectually sluggish to bother with such things."

Of course, the history of philosophy is littered with people who used words in highly idiosyncratic ways, so this would suggest that you've not been very interested in learning the history of philosophy in any depth.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By GE Morton
#351159
Terrapin Station wrote: February 28th, 2020, 2:15 pm
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 12:44 pm
That is absurd. A goal is something one desires to pursue. If pursuing X it is not better than not pursuing it, then X is no longer a goal. Similarly, if one desires X, then securing X is better than not securing it. If it isn't, then one no longer desires X.
What you're talking about here is the way that an individual can feel about pursuing things, about whether they should pursue things when they have a goal, etc.
You're not getting it. One may wonder whether he should pursue a particular X to secure Y (because he is unsure whether X will get him any closer to Y), but if he is wondering whether he should pursue Y then he is wondering whether he should abandon that as a goal. As long as it remains his goal, then he will be better off by pursuing it. Being "better off" just means that more of one's goals and desires are fulfilled.
"A way that an individual feels" isn't "an objective fact."
True. But that Alfie considers Y to be a worthy goal is an objective fact, and that he will be better off having secured it is also an objective fact. His feelings are subjective; that he has them is objective.
By GE Morton
#351165
Terrapin Station wrote: February 28th, 2020, 2:25 pm
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 1:35 pm The definitions state the accepted, understood meanings.
Definitions are the text or sound strings that we correlate with meanings. Meanings consist of the mental act of making associations where something like a text string implies or suggests an association with something else. That association doesn't occur anywhere but in minds. So no, it doesn't make ontological sense to say that definitions are meanings.
I didn't say, "Definitions are meanings." I said, "Defintitions state meanings. Just as "Paris is the capital of France" states that Paris is the capital of France. Where the association between a word and its meaning occurs is irrelevant to what that meaning is. Definitions state those meanings, and one can point to the things that are the meanings (of most concrete nouns and verbs).
We haven't the faintest idea what meaning anyone else is associating with terms, sounds, gestures, etc. That doesn't matter. We go by observables instead.
Of course we know that. If Alfie points to a dog when presented with the word "dog," then we know he associates that word with that object. We know nothing about what is in his head, and don't care.

This is going in circles, TP. Your conception of meanings results in a reductio ad absurdum, which you can't seem to grasp.
By GE Morton
#351168
Terrapin Station wrote: February 28th, 2020, 2:18 pm
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 12:47 pm PS: And, yes, it is an objective fact. It is a logical truth, and all logical truths are objective.
Logic is a way that individuals think about implicational relations. It's not something found in the world outside of thinking.

So no, that's not objective.
Heh. Well, no propositions, no communication, no arguments, no science or philosophy is found "outside the world of thinking." If that is what "objective" requires for you, then nothing is objective, and you've rendered the term useless. You have a facility for absurdities of that sort.
By Peter Holmes
#351173
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 1:22 pm ,
Peter Holmes wrote: February 28th, 2020, 5:39 am
Thanks. I must apologise for misunderstanding your argument. Your fire and gosoline example explains what you mean by 'ought':

If one wishes to put out a fire, one ought not pour gasoline on it.

This is a factual assertion, not an obligation, nor a value-judgement - least of all a moral claim. The word 'ought' here has none of the significance I'd been assuming. In effect, it means 'must'.
Not necessarily "must" (though in the fire example it does mean "must"). The instrumental sense of "ought" just means that doing X is an effective, or perhaps necessary, means of attaining Y. So, "You ought to do X" just means "Doing X will get you closer to Y." "You ought not do X" means, "Doing X will hamper or prevent your attainment of Y." All of those claims can be objective.

And of course I agree those are "factual assertions, not obligations or value-judgments." But they are moral claims, if the goal is a moral one.
Okay. Your claim is: a factual assertion whose purpose is to achieve a moral goal (which is subjective) is a moral assertion - so that 'Doing X will get you closer to Y' can be a moral assertion. But this is sophistry.

A moral assertion expresses a judgement about the moral rightness or wrongness of an action, and is therefore subjective. Examples might be:
'Y is morally good,' and 'It's morally right to do X in order to get closer to Y'. These are not factual assertions.

The factual assertion that doing X will get you closer to Y, which is objective and so true or false, has no moral implication - no expression of value whatsoever. To call it a moral assertion is false.

There is nothing epistemologically "special," and certainly nothing esoteric, about "moral" propositions, moral principles or rules. I take "morality" to be, simply, the inquiry into finding workable, effective principles and rules governing interactions between moral agents in a social setting, with the aim of maximizing the welfare of all. Principles and rules having that aim are "moral" principles and rules.
But that we should or ought to to do these things and have this goal - those are the moral issues - the matters of judgement. And moral and ethical debate is usually about them - not so much the practical, factual matters you think constitute moral theory and enquiry. What you're talking about is public or social policy - or legislation and law.

The exercise is analogous to devising a workable, effective set of principles and rules governing a highway system, with the aim of assuring that all drivers reach their destinations quickly and safely. Those principles and rules are "traffic rules." There is nothing mystical, or even mysterious, about either, and in both cases whether the principles do or do not advance their goals is an empirical question with objective answers.
I don't know why you think anyone believes morality is esoteric, mystical or mysterious. What straw man do you have in mind?
And, pari passu with 'if one wishes to preserve and advance the welfare of all agents, one ought not to kill people'. (Murder is unlawful killing, which introduces issues that beg the question.)
More broadly, "murder" means "unjustified killing." One may still commit murder even if there are no laws. A moral theory will need to spell out when killing is and is not justified.
And those will be matters of judgement, belief or opinion, and so subjective. Morality is not objective.
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#351176
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 2:32 pm You're not getting it. One may wonder whether he should pursue a particular X to secure Y (because he is unsure whether X will get him any closer to Y), but if he is wondering whether he should pursue Y then he is wondering whether he should abandon that as a goal. As long as it remains his goal, then he will be better off by pursuing it. Being "better off" just means that more of one's goals and desires are fulfilled.
Nope. You're not getting it. It's not preferable in any objective way, so that it supports a normative, to have one's goals and desires fulfilled rather than to not have them fulfilled. An individual may very well prefer to have their goals and desires fulfilled, but that doesn't make it an objective fact that they should have them fulfilled.

We can say that it's an objective fact that x will fulfill goal y, but that doesn't lend itself to saying that it's an objective fact that one should do x.
True. But that Alfie considers Y to be a worthy goal is an objective fact,
That's a subjective fact in my terminology. It's a fact about Alfie's mind.
and that he will be better off having secured it is also an objective fact. His feelings are subjective; that he has them is objective.
He would only be better off in someone's opinion. It can't be an objective fact (that is, it can't obtain extramentally) that anyone is "better off" or that anything is better than anything else.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Belindi
#351190
GEMorton wrote:
Love is the default, and mercy, pity, and peace are love-based reactions to circumstances.

When I say "love is the default" I mean the more loving individuals have the choice to be fearful and have the choice to be loving. Those who choose fear are unfree as they lack that choice but must react from fear.
"Choose fear?" If they have a choice, then they are free, are they not? But it sounds like you're saying that some people have free will, others don't. A tough position to defend, I suspect.
Reacting to an emotion is unfree. Love is more free because love must include taking courage, care, and trouble to acquire knowledge and best judgement .
It's not that some have Free Will while other don't, but that some are more free than others because those who are more free are can love i.e. they can take courage, care and trouble to control their fear reactions and act from reason.
User avatar
By chewybrian
#351194
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 2:32 pm You're not getting it. One may wonder whether he should pursue a particular X to secure Y (because he is unsure whether X will get him any closer to Y), but if he is wondering whether he should pursue Y then he is wondering whether he should abandon that as a goal. As long as it remains his goal, then he will be better off by pursuing it. Being "better off" just means that more of one's goals and desires are fulfilled.
Then why do so many lottery winners crash and burn? Aren't they able to reach many more of their goals and fulfill more of their desires? But, most people don't really even know what they want, as much as what they DON"T want. They had a scapegoat when the man was holding them down, and they knew that everything would be great if they could just break out of that rent trap and quit living paycheck to paycheck. But, they had no real idea of how to be happy, just an excuse of why they were not happy. Then, they realize, when given the chance, that they don't even know what, if anything, would make them happy. They have to take the blame for their unhappiness, which makes them even more unhappy.

They were free when they thought they were not, and they are still free after the big win, but they are not equipped to handle the freedom. I doubt many people would be happier by having their goals fulfilled, unless they really had their act together before the fulfillment. If your goals were to be a good person, help others and such, then maybe...
Favorite Philosopher: Epictetus Location: Florida man
By GE Morton
#351206
Peter Holmes wrote: February 28th, 2020, 4:17 pm
Okay. Your claim is: a factual assertion whose purpose is to achieve a moral goal (which is subjective) is a moral assertion - so that 'Doing X will get you closer to Y' can be a moral assertion. But this is sophistry.
Oh? In what way? Sophistry is an invalid argument, usually a subtle one, that aims to deceive. Yes, a principle or rule formulated to further some purpose takes on the name of that purpose. This quite conventional --- laws aimed to improve traffic flow and safety are "traffic laws." Rules adopted to govern the game of baseball are "baseball rules." Etc. Rules aimed at accomplishing some moral goal are "moral rules." Where do you see deception in that?
A moral assertion expresses a judgement about the moral rightness or wrongness of an action, and is therefore subjective. Examples might be:
'Y is morally good,' and 'It's morally right to do X in order to get closer to Y'. These are not factual assertions.
Well, first, "morally good" is a confusion. "Good" and "bad" may express approval or disapproval of an action (and are thus subjective), but they don't determine, or express, the rightness of wrongness of an action, which is objective. An act is morally right if it is consistent with a moral goal; a rule is morally right if it advances a moral goal. Whether they are or not is is objective.

Judgments, BTW are not true or false, objective or subjective. Judgments are "mental" acts, or events --- the act of interpreting and evaluating some state of affairs, or perhaps some argument or statement. It is the proposition expressed in a judgment that is subjective or objective. If I say, "It is my judgment that Trump is a liar," I'm saying two things: that I've evaluated his statements and concluded he is a liar, and that he is a liar. The former is a report on an action of mine; it is subjective, though it may be true, but the latter is objective.

All evaluations of states of affairs involve judgments. A moral judgment is a judgment that some act violates or complies with some moral rule. But that someone judges an act (morally) right or wrong doesn't entail that it is right or wrong. It is only right or wrong if it furthers or thwarts a moral goal, and whether it does or not is objective.
The factual assertion that doing X will get you closer to Y, which is objective and so true or false, has no moral implication - no expression of value whatsoever. To call it a moral assertion is false.
Well, Peter, X and Y there are variables, place-holders. Whether Y has moral implications depends upon what substantive is substituted for Y. If Y is a moral goal, then it, and X, have moral implications.
There is nothing epistemologically "special," and certainly nothing esoteric, about "moral" propositions, moral principles or rules. I take "morality" to be, simply, the inquiry into finding workable, effective principles and rules governing interactions between moral agents in a social setting, with the aim of maximizing the welfare of all. Principles and rules having that aim are "moral" principles and rules.
But that we should or ought to to do these things and have this goal - those are the moral issues - the matters of judgement. And moral and ethical debate is usually about them - not so much the practical, factual matters you think constitute moral theory and enquiry. What you're talking about is public or social policy - or legislation and law.
Well, the question of whether we "ought" to adopt that goal is not a moral one, but a pragmatic one. Nor do I agree that ethical debate is "usually about them" (goals). It is usually about what principles and rules hold the most promise of attaining that goal. But I make no claim that we "should" or "ought" adopt that goal. I make no argument intended to persuade anyone to adopt it. I take it as obvious that, historically, the aim of anything we're willing to call a "moral code" has been to secure and advance human well-being. And I take it as self-evident that some principles and rules governing human interactions are necessary for that goal to be attained. Those principles and rules can, of course, result in laws and public policies. But the moral questions need to be answered before any such laws or policies are adopted. Laws and public policies are as capable, and as likely, to be immoral as moral.

So if you disagree with that goal, think it not worth pursuing, then you'll either have a very different conception of what morality is, or no interest in a moral code and no need for one.
More broadly, "murder" means "unjustified killing." One may still commit murder even if there are no laws. A moral theory will need to spell out when killing is and is not justified.
And those will be matters of judgement, belief or opinion, and so subjective. Morality is not objective.
Every matter is one of judgment and opinion. But some are also matters of fact. (See above).
By GE Morton
#351207
Belindi wrote: February 28th, 2020, 6:24 pm GEMorton wrote:
"Choose fear?" If they have a choice, then they are free, are they not? But it sounds like you're saying that some people have free will, others don't. A tough position to defend, I suspect.
Reacting to an emotion is unfree. Love is more free because love must include taking courage, care, and trouble to acquire knowledge and best judgement .
It's not that some have Free Will while other don't, but that some are more free than others because those who are more free are can love i.e. they can take courage, care and trouble to control their fear reactions and act from reason.
Love is an emotion too, Belindi. Sometimes love can override fear, sometimes fear overrides love. No one is free from emotions, but everyone is free to act or not act on them.
By GE Morton
#351208
Terrapin Station wrote: February 28th, 2020, 4:32 pm
Nope. You're not getting it. It's not preferable in any objective way . . .
Oh, you're right. No preferences are objective. That Alfie does prefer X to Y, however, is objective, and that he will be better off by attaining X than Y is also objective.
. . . so that it supports a normative, to have one's goals and desires fulfilled rather than to not have them fulfilled. An individual may very well prefer to have their goals and desires fulfilled, but that doesn't make it an objective fact that they should have them fulfilled.
It does if the goal of the "shoulds" and "oughts" in question is promoting human well-being. If it isn't, if your goal is perhaps punishing or depriving or tormenting him, then he should not be allowed to realize his desires. What you should or should not do depends on the goal you have in mind. Whatever that may be, whether one ought or ought not do X is objective --- X either will or will not advance you toward that goal.
True. But that Alfie considers Y to be a worthy goal is an objective fact,
That's a subjective fact in my terminology. It's a fact about Alfie's mind.
No. It is a conclusion drawn from his observable behavior. If I see Alfie ordering a chocolate ice cream cone at Baskin-Robbins, I'll conclude he prefers chocolate to vanilla or Rocky Road, at least on that occasion. I need know nothing about what's going on in his head.
He would only be better off in someone's opinion. It can't be an objective fact (that is, it can't obtain extramentally) that anyone is "better off" or that anything is better than anything else.
Sorry, but it is. If Alfie considers himself better off with a chocolate ice cream cone than a vanilla one, then he is better off. His well-being depends only upon satisfaction of his interests and desires, and that he considers himself better off with chocolate is evident from his behavior. Anyone else's opinion of whether he is better off are irrelevant.
By GE Morton
#351211
chewybrian wrote: February 28th, 2020, 7:03 pm
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 2:32 pm You're not getting it. One may wonder whether he should pursue a particular X to secure Y (because he is unsure whether X will get him any closer to Y), but if he is wondering whether he should pursue Y then he is wondering whether he should abandon that as a goal. As long as it remains his goal, then he will be better off by pursuing it. Being "better off" just means that more of one's goals and desires are fulfilled.
Then why do so many lottery winners crash and burn? Aren't they able to reach many more of their goals and fulfill more of their desires? But, most people don't really even know what they want, as much as what they DON"T want. They had a scapegoat when the man was holding them down, and they knew that everything would be great if they could just break out of that rent trap and quit living paycheck to paycheck. But, they had no real idea of how to be happy, just an excuse of why they were not happy. Then, they realize, when given the chance, that they don't even know what, if anything, would make them happy. They have to take the blame for their unhappiness, which makes them even more unhappy.

They were free when they thought they were not, and they are still free after the big win, but they are not equipped to handle the freedom. I doubt many people would be happier by having their goals fulfilled, unless they really had their act together before the fulfillment. If your goals were to be a good person, help others and such, then maybe...
What you say is largely true, but you're confusing being happier with being better off. I'm quite sure those unhappy lottery winners would agree they are better off after the win. People can indeed be mistaken about how much satisfaction attaining a goal will actually yield. But unless it yields no satisfaction they are better off, and had they not pursued it they would not have learned how overrated it was.
By Peter Holmes
#351218
GE Morton wrote: February 28th, 2020, 10:47 pm
Peter Holmes wrote: February 28th, 2020, 4:17 pm
Okay. Your claim is: a factual assertion whose purpose is to achieve a moral goal (which is subjective) is a moral assertion - so that 'Doing X will get you closer to Y' can be a moral assertion. But this is sophistry.
Oh? In what way? Sophistry is an invalid argument, usually a subtle one, that aims to deceive. Yes, a principle or rule formulated to further some purpose takes on the name of that purpose. This quite conventional --- laws aimed to improve traffic flow and safety are "traffic laws." Rules adopted to govern the game of baseball are "baseball rules." Etc. Rules aimed at accomplishing some moral goal are "moral rules." Where do you see deception in that?
The deception is in your slippery use of terms. Rules are commands, which are not factual, and have no truth-value. To call a rule 'objective' is a simple misuse of the word 'objective', which, as you say, properly refers to assertions. That a rule exists may be a fact, of course, but that doesn't make the rule objective. And it follows that rules aimed at establishing any goal, including a moral goal, are not objective. They're just rules. Call them 'moral rules' if you wish, but please don't pretend that their existence means that moral assertions are objective. That's sophistry.

I have more to say about the terminological tangle you're peddling, but I have no time at the moment.
User avatar
By chewybrian
#351223
GE Morton wrote: February 29th, 2020, 12:00 am
chewybrian wrote: February 28th, 2020, 7:03 pm

Then why do so many lottery winners crash and burn? Aren't they able to reach many more of their goals and fulfill more of their desires? But, most people don't really even know what they want, as much as what they DON"T want. They had a scapegoat when the man was holding them down, and they knew that everything would be great if they could just break out of that rent trap and quit living paycheck to paycheck. But, they had no real idea of how to be happy, just an excuse of why they were not happy. Then, they realize, when given the chance, that they don't even know what, if anything, would make them happy. They have to take the blame for their unhappiness, which makes them even more unhappy.

They were free when they thought they were not, and they are still free after the big win, but they are not equipped to handle the freedom. I doubt many people would be happier by having their goals fulfilled, unless they really had their act together before the fulfillment. If your goals were to be a good person, help others and such, then maybe...
What you say is largely true, but you're confusing being happier with being better off. I'm quite sure those unhappy lottery winners would agree they are better off after the win. People can indeed be mistaken about how much satisfaction attaining a goal will actually yield. But unless it yields no satisfaction they are better off, and had they not pursued it they would not have learned how overrated it was.
It's not confusing to me. I think you are better off if you are happier, and that gaining material things or meeting external goals is a very shallow pursuit that brings little lasting happiness. The world, and even a bastion of philosophy like this, is filled with people who apply logic in pursuit of these goals, yet take no time to become emotionally educated, or to consider if the goals fulfill them or not. When they reach a goal and still feel empty, rather than reflecting on why they feel empty, they simply carry on to the next external goal that they assume will make them feel better.
Favorite Philosopher: Epictetus Location: Florida man
By Belindi
#351224
Peter Holmes wrote:
Love is an emotion too, Belindi. Sometimes love can override fear, sometimes fear overrides love. No one is free from emotions, but everyone is free to act or not act on them.
Love is not an emotion it's a set of motivations, intentions, and behaviours. Love is invariably present unless fear has banished it.The probability of motivation, intention, or behaviour becoming actual varies with individuals and cultures, and indeed sometimes the raw emotion of fear overcomes an individual and a culture. Nazism is a culture where fear of others has overcome a significant number of individuals in a society, and love is swamped by fear and its aftermath. Indeed some beliefs can and do raise fear to the extent the individual concerned is too fearful to be able to love.

Fear is emotion which is usually cognitive . By "cognitive" I refer to raw fear translated by some belief about what is to blame for the perceived threat ; then raw fear turns into malevolence, jealousy, spite, murder, callousness, greed, timidity, bullying, stupidity, etc.
  • 1
  • 39
  • 40
  • 41
  • 42
  • 43
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


My misgivings about the Golden Rule

How about a slight variation on the Golden Rule: […]

It’s not just about victim blaming for showing exc[…]

Hitler's model - that relied on plundering the[…]

Look at nature and you'll see hierarchies ever[…]