Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
By Peter Holmes
#350110
Terrapin Station wrote: February 18th, 2020, 7:20 pm
Greta wrote: February 18th, 2020, 7:17 pm There is only one way to make morality objective, and that is to know every single knock-on effect of every event. Each "good" claimed by any person or group simply refers to a geographical and temporal span. If you know what will ultimately bring the greatest good, not in 10 years' time or 100 years' time, but a thousand or a million years' time.
Even if you could do that, how would you get past the fact that whether anything is "good" is still a mental assessment that individuals have to make?

There's no way to get past that fact.
Couldn't agree more. And I wonder why this glaringly obvious fact is so hard for many people to grasp.
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350116
GE Morton wrote: February 19th, 2020, 11:10 pm Yes, it does. The truth conditions for a proposition
The proposition isn't public. Propositions are meanings. Meanings are not public.
are the observable states-of-affairs-in-the-world which, if they obtain, make the proposition true.
You're completely ignoring the need to make a judgment about correspondence, because you're not actually analyzing how the marks I'm producing by typing, the sounds I'd make via uttering speech, etc. both (a) amount to meaning rather than simply being marks or sounds, and (b) obtain any sort of relations to things that aren't the marks or sounds in question.

The only way that both (a) and (b) work are by an individual thinking about such things. But thinking isn't public.

You're also probably projecting language, as that seems to be a common thing to do when talking about truth theory a la disquotational truth theory and other versions of correspondence especially. It's common to say things like "'The cat is on the mat' (is true) iff the cat is on the mat"--as if the second occurrence of "the cat is on the mat," the one not in extra quotation marks, is something that obtains more or less linguistically, so that it simply matches the first "the cat is on the mat," the one in extra quotation marks, the one that represents the proposition.

The problem with this is that a cat being on a mat is nothing like language, and it's nothing like meaning. In order to say that the extramental cat on the mat matches a proposition, it's necessary to make a judgment about the way the observed extramental facts "connect" to the proposition, from a particular individual's perspective--because we're talking about their meaning, their observations, from their unique spatio-temporal perspective, with their perceptual faculties working as they do, per their view of what it is for the observed facts to "match" the proposition. Those are the truth conditions for a proposition.
Nope.
Yep.
The truth of a proposition has nothing to do with anything "in people's heads." "Paris is the capital of France" is true no matter what anyone thinks
Okay, so instead of going over and over this, let's get down to the brass tacks of your view. Let's say that we have "Paris is the capital of France" written or in sound (like a recording) or something.

Now, what exactly happens for the marks on the paper or the sound to have "true" or "false" assigned to it relative to non-mental things in the world.

Remember, if you say anything that involves people doing things where they need to be mentally active--making observations, making decisions, making judgments, etc. you're going to get a buzzer, because you're claiming that truth ascriptions have NOTHING to do with ANYTHING in people's heads.

So we've got the marks on paper or a computer screen or a sound recording of "Paris is the capital of France." What happens next so that we have a truth-value ascription on your view?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350119
I will address this, too, at the moment, because I'm going to bet my house that you'll not do the "getting down to brass tacks" bit about how this is supposed to work, exactly, in detail, on your view so that is has nothing to do with anything going on in anyone's heads (which would mean that we're not going to get back to this otherwise:)
GE Morton wrote: February 19th, 2020, 11:10 pm
Terrapin Station wrote: February 19th, 2020, 8:02 pm "Suitably situated" in whose judgment?"
No one's. No judgment is involved. Either Alfie is or is not in a position to make the required observation
So we say that "That rock is shale" is an "objective proposition" because it's "verifiable by any suitably situated person." (I'm not using "Paris is the capital of France" as the example because I think that's a horrible example to use for your goals for reasons I won't detail here. It would be far better to stick to a simple example like "That rock is shale.")

So then we take 50 geologists and ask them, "Is that rock shale?"

10 say "No, that rock isn't shale." 40 say, "Yes, that rock is is shale."

We ask the 10 to look at it better, do further research, etc., but no matter what, they come back and say, "No, that rock isn't shale."

Now, presumably either the proposition isn't objective after all, because not everyone verified it, or we need to say that the 10 people in question weren't "suitably situated" after all.

You're saying that whether they're "suitably situated" isn't a judgment. Well, what decides whether the people in question are "suitably situated" then? Simply whether they verify the proposition? "For any proposition, P, you're suitably situated if you verify it, otherwise you're not suitably situated." That can't be right, can it?

And certainly we wouldn't say that any proposition's objectivity hinges on their being unanimous verification of it, right?

So how do we wind up with "suitably situated" without making a judgment? What determines "suitably situated" exactly?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350120
Oops, typo: "And certainly we wouldn't say that any proposition's objectivity hinges on there being unanimous verification of it, right?"
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Steve3007
#350121
Terrapin Station wrote:So we say that "That rock is shale" is an "objective proposition" because it's "verifiable by any suitably situated person." (I'm not using "Paris is the capital of France" as the example because I think that's a horrible example to use for your goals for reasons I won't detail here. It would be far better to stick to a simple example like "That rock is shale.")
Neither of them seem to me to be good examples to use to illustrate GE Morton's point about truth conditions being public. Something like "it is raining" seems better to me.
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350122
Steve3007 wrote: February 20th, 2020, 9:30 am
Terrapin Station wrote:So we say that "That rock is shale" is an "objective proposition" because it's "verifiable by any suitably situated person." (I'm not using "Paris is the capital of France" as the example because I think that's a horrible example to use for your goals for reasons I won't detail here. It would be far better to stick to a simple example like "That rock is shale.")
Neither of them seem to me to be good examples to use to illustrate GE Morton's point about truth conditions being public. Something like "it is raining" seems better to me.
That would work fine, too.

So you ask 50 people, and at least a few of them say "It is not raining."

Is that no longer an objective proposition then?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Steve3007
#350123
Terrapin Station wrote:So you ask 50 people, and at least a few of them say "It is not raining."

Is that no longer an objective proposition then?
I'd say it's still an objective proposition because it's a proposition about objects - about a proposed state of affairs in a proposed real world. If two objective propositions contradict each other that doesn't mean that they're not both objective propositions.
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350126
Steve3007 wrote: February 20th, 2020, 10:03 am
Terrapin Station wrote:So you ask 50 people, and at least a few of them say "It is not raining."

Is that no longer an objective proposition then?
I'd say it's still an objective proposition because it's a proposition about objects - about a proposed state of affairs in a proposed real world. If two objective propositions contradict each other that doesn't mean that they're not both objective propositions.
"Objective proposition" is a bad term for that, though, for a number of reasons. First, usually the "adjective noun" form suggests that the adjective is telling us a property of the noun as an existent. For example, "red ball," "tall man," "reticulated python." In those cases, "red," "tall," and "reticulated" are properties that the noun they modify "possesses." But with "objective proposition," the proposition itself isn't an object or objective. The way you and others are attempting to use this term is akin to saying, "Red book" when the book itself is in no way red, but is rather a book about the color red. If you were to say, "That's a red book" to someone, you shouldn't be surprised when they say, "Red? What are you talking about. My copy of the book has no red. The cover is black with white lettering. The pages are white with black ink."

Or once again, this is an example of use/mention confusion.

Another reason it's a bad term is that it knocks (at least ontological) idealists out of the conversation. Ontological idealists don't think that anything is an object in the relevant, mind-independent sense. So they'd disagree that "It is raining" or "That rock is shale" is an objective proposition in the way you're using the term, because a fortiori, they'd say that nothing can be an objective proposition in that sense.

Now, if we're realists, we're going to believe that propositions can be ABOUT objective things, but that doesn't make the proposition itself objective (avoiding use/mention confusion).

And on my view, propositions are ABOUT objective things only subjectively. That's because ALL aboutness is a subjective phenomenon--it's one of the unique things our minds do. There is no extramental aboutness to be had. Aboutness is a way we think. Hence the infamous slogan, "Intentionality is the mark of the mental." ("Intentionality," in this philosophical usage, being another term for aboutness.)
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Terrapin Station
#350130
Oh, and I forgot to add, since propositions are about objective things only subjectively, there's not going to be any universal agreement on (and it's certainly not an objective fact) whether a given proposition is about an objective thing or not.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Steve3007
#350133
Terrapin Station wrote:"Objective proposition" is a bad term for that, though, for a number of reasons. First, usually the "adjective noun" form suggests that the adjective is telling us a property of the noun as an existent. For example, "red ball," "tall man," "reticulated python." In those cases, "red," "tall," and "reticulated" are properties that the noun they modify "possesses." But with "objective proposition," the proposition itself isn't an object or objective. The way you and others are attempting to use this term is akin to saying, "Red book" when the book itself is in no way red, but is rather a book about the color red. If you were to say, "That's a red book" to someone, you shouldn't be surprised when they say, "Red? What are you talking about. My copy of the book has no red. The cover is black with white lettering. The pages are white with black ink."
OK, I see your grammatical point. So the solution to that problem could be to make it clear that the term "objective proposition" is shorthand for "proposition about object(s)". Just as "Red book" could be shorthand for "Book about the colour red". Yes, when the nature of the shorthand is not made clear it might be misleading but that's shorthand for you. Shorthands are often misleading if not explained. But there's nothing wrong with using them. If somebody on the News says "The Whitehouse has released a statement", we don't all say "Huh?!? How can a house, whatever its colour, release a statement?". We understand what that shorthand means.
Or once again, this is an example of use/mention confusion.
Or, that phrase that has been used many times "mistaking the map for the territory". But that can easily be cleared up. If I point to a map and say "Look! That's Africa!" and you say "No it's not. It's a map of Africa" the misunderstanding can easily be cleared up.
Another reason it's a bad term is that it knocks (at least ontological) idealists out of the conversation. Ontological idealists don't think that anything is an object in the relevant, mind-independent sense. So they'd disagree that "It is raining" or "That rock is shale" is an objective proposition in the way you're using the term, because a fortiori, they'd say that nothing can be an objective proposition in that sense.
I don't think that those idealists have to take the position that nothing can be an objective proposition in that sense. They can just take the position that people who make objective propositions are delusional (and in my experience that is what they do). Even if we take the view that no objects exist, we can still make propositions about objects. I and others can make propositions about unicorns even though I don't believe they exist.
Now, if we're realists, we're going to believe that propositions can be ABOUT objective things, but that doesn't make the proposition itself objective (avoiding use/mention confusion).
So, as above, we can take "objective proposition" to be shorthand for "proposition about object(s)"
And on my view, propositions are ABOUT objective things only subjectively. That's because ALL aboutness is a subjective phenomenon--it's one of the unique things our minds do. There is no extramental aboutness to be had. Aboutness is a way we think. Hence the infamous slogan, "Intentionality is the mark of the mental." ("Intentionality," in this philosophical usage, being another term for aboutness.)
I agree to the extent that when I make a proposition like "it is raining" or "there is a chair" I am doing so as a result of my subjective sensations. In that sense, they are about objective things subjectively. If I said "there is a chair" and everyone else in the room disagreed, and then I reached out to touch the chair and my hand "disagreed" with my eyes, I would doubt the soundness of that proposition about that object.
Oh, and I forgot to add, since propositions are about objective things only subjectively, there's not going to be any universal agreement on (and it's certainly not an objective fact) whether a given proposition is about an objective thing or not.
I agree.
By GE Morton
#350137
Peter Holmes wrote: February 20th, 2020, 6:17 am GE Morton wrote:

'Morality is objective to the extent propositions asserting moral principles have public truth conditions, just as for any other category of propositions.'

What are the public truth conditions for the assertion 'slavery is morally wrong'? What, independent from opinion, would make that true, the absence of which would make it false?
Moral propositions are true or false depending upon whether or not they further an agreed-upon goal. Whether they do or do not further that goal is (usually) publicly determinable. If so, then they are objective.

"Slavery is wrong" is true and objective if one conceives the aim, or goal, of a moral theory to be establishing rules of conduct which allow all agents within its universe to maximize their welfare. The welfare of a person enslaved is greatly reduced, thwarting that goal. Hence "slavery is wrong" is true and objective.

Of course, the choice of a goal is subjective. But someone who proposes a different goal will be obliged to defend it.
By GE Morton
#350138
Greta wrote: February 20th, 2020, 5:02 am
What I said had nothing whatsoever to do with metaphysics. Please try again, and reply to what I wrote, not what you wished I had written.
What you said was, "Actually, objective morality does require omniscience."

Sorry Greta, but omniscience does invoke metaphysics. Only transcendental beings can be omniscient. My response was directly on point.
That's what you said, not me. I just refuted the idea that any person or groups of people can determine an objective morality. It will always be skewed, always subjective.
Well, you denied it, but hardly refuted it. A refutation requires an argument, not a mere repetition of the claim.

Objectivity has nothing to do with omniscience or anything else transcendental. It merely means that the truth conditions are public. A proposition asserting a moral rule is objective if its truth conditions are public. Moral principles and rules assume no values; they are indifferent to values. They only assume that people do value various things, and that their welfare is measured by the extent to which they secure the things they value, whatever those may be.
By GE Morton
#350139
Peter Holmes wrote: February 20th, 2020, 7:19 am
Terrapin Station wrote: February 18th, 2020, 7:20 pm

Even if you could do that, how would you get past the fact that whether anything is "good" is still a mental assessment that individuals have to make?

There's no way to get past that fact.
Couldn't agree more. And I wonder why this glaringly obvious fact is so hard for many people to grasp.
I agree too. But what is "good" is a question for axiology, not morality.
By GE Morton
#350140
Terrapin Station wrote: February 20th, 2020, 9:09 am
The proposition isn't public. Propositions are meanings. Meanings are not public.
To persist with that claim you need to deal with the reductio outlined earlier.
You're completely ignoring the need to make a judgment about correspondence, because you're not actually analyzing how the marks I'm producing by typing, the sounds I'd make via uttering speech, etc. both (a) amount to meaning rather than simply being marks or sounds, and (b) obtain any sort of relations to things that aren't the marks or sounds in question.
I answered that question many posts back. The association between a word and a thing --- the thing that is its meaning --- is learned, initially via ostensive definition (by pointing to something). That is how all young children learn language.

We're going in circles, TP. Deal with the reductio.
By GE Morton
#350141
Terrapin Station wrote: February 20th, 2020, 9:27 am I will address this, too, at the moment, because I'm going to bet my house that you'll not do the "getting down to brass tacks" bit about how this is supposed to work, exactly, in detail, on your view so that is has nothing to do with anything going on in anyone's heads (which would mean that we're not going to get back to this otherwise:)
GE Morton wrote: February 19th, 2020, 11:10 pm
No one's. No judgment is involved. Either Alfie is or is not in a position to make the required observation
So we say that "That rock is shale" is an "objective proposition" because it's "verifiable by any suitably situated person." (I'm not using "Paris is the capital of France" as the example because I think that's a horrible example to use for your goals for reasons I won't detail here. It would be far better to stick to a simple example like "That rock is shale.")
Please set forth those reasons.
So then we take 50 geologists and ask them, "Is that rock shale?"

10 say "No, that rock isn't shale." 40 say, "Yes, that rock is is shale."

We ask the 10 to look at it better, do further research, etc., but no matter what, they come back and say, "No, that rock isn't shale."

Now, presumably either the proposition isn't objective after all, because not everyone verified it, or we need to say that the 10 people in question weren't "suitably situated" after all.
Whether they agree or not is irrelevant. What makes the proposition objective is the mere fact that they are all basing their verdicts on examination of the rock. That they can't agree merely means they need to examine it more carefully. A proposition is objective if its truth conditions are public, which they are in this case. There is no requirement that all observers agree. A subjective proposition, in contrast, would be, "This rock is beautiful."
You're saying that whether they're "suitably situated" isn't a judgment. Well, what decides whether the people in question are "suitably situated" then? Simply whether they verify the proposition? "For any proposition, P, you're suitably situated if you verify it, otherwise you're not suitably situated." That can't be right, can it?
A person is suitably situated if he is in a position to examine the rock --- to inspect it, run tests on it, etc. You're being obtuse, TP.
  • 1
  • 22
  • 23
  • 24
  • 25
  • 26
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021