Leontiskos wrote: ↑June 24th, 2022, 12:34 am
Thanks, and welcome to the forum. That was the most cogent presentation of moral non-cognitivism that I have seen on this forum (which incidentally is a forum full of moral non-cognitivists).
Let me just poke at two things:
Astro Cat wrote: ↑June 17th, 2022, 10:06 pmI think that moral beliefs behave philosophically a lot like preferences. So let me talk about preferences for a moment. When we make a preference statement, it's usually non-controversial to say that the preference statement isn't propositional (it doesn't have a truth value). If I snack on a string cheese and say "String cheese is tasty*," I haven't said something that corresponds to mind-independent reality; it's neither true nor false. It's a preference statement. After all, what corresponds to reality about "being tasty," and how does the string cheese do it? How do we check reality for it even in principle?
(*-by this I mean it tastes good, not just that it has physical properties that activate taste buds)
I am trying to understand your argument here. I have a few options:
- Moral beliefs are non-propositional because moral beliefs are preferences, and all preferences are non-propositional.
- "String cheese is tasty" is non-propositional because it does not correspond to mind-independent reality, and all propositional statements correspond to mind-independent reality.
- There is no conceivable object of correspondence for the assertion, "String cheese is tasty," therefore it cannot be propositional.
Is there one of these that you are more committed to defending than the others?
Thanks for the welcome!
Ok, thank you for making me do this. I feel like this helps me understand my own thoughts as much as it might help you understand what I'm even trying to say.
I don't like the first one because it feels really bold. I feel like all preferences are probably non-propositional but it feels like I'd have to do a lot more work to do that one.
I want to agree with the second one, but it contains the issue that's being disputed below, so I'll skip that one for now too. It also feels like there would have to be a lot of work to support the second half. Off the top of my head I feel like I can introspect things about my mind that would be true, then I would have to really nail down what's meant by "mind-independent reality" if I want to be able to say things like "I experience happiness," which feels propositional. So, I'll shy away from that one too.
I think I like this third one best. I should clarify that my non-cognitivism is more provisional, and so I'm making a weaker claim: I have yet to encounter a convincing argument there is an object of correspondence is closer to my position than "there is no..." (e.g., I am unconvinced there is one rather than affirming the negative).
Leontiskos wrote:
Astro Cat wrote: ↑June 23rd, 2022, 1:40 amGood_Egg wrote: ↑June 21st, 2022, 7:19 pmAstro Cat wrote: ↑June 20th, 2022, 1:24 pmIn the same way that some people say "one ought not to steal," and we know they don't just mean that they themselves believe one ought not to steal but that in general one ought not to steal, S1 is supposed to represent the same sort of general statement in structure.
Sure - and similarly there are vegetarians who think everybody should be vegetarian and there are vegetarians who are content that it is a good choice for themselves.
But if that's a meaningful distinction, as it seems we both think it is, then how can you think that an ought-statement is identical to or nothing but a statement of personal preference ?
I don't think that moral statements are exactly like preference statements: I have only argued that they behave similarly philosophically.
As we know, we care more about or moral statements than we do our preference statements. I care more about feeding the hungry than I do about string cheese tasting good. I believe you bring this up yourself down below, so I will speak more on it there.
[...]
Yes, we feel things like guilt, shame, outrage, shock, etc. when it comes to our moral statements. So, I don't think that moral preferences are the same as food or color preferences. Yet, I do still think our moral feelings are a kind of preference. I think they're preferences that we feel strongly about and which involve concepts like suffering and altruism; whereas other preferences do not. Sort of like an "all rectangles are squares but not all squares are rectangles" sort of situation: moral preferences are (maybe) preferences, but not all preferences are moral preferences.
It is true that some preferences are more strongly held and some preferences are more weakly held, but it seems to me that the difference between Good_Egg's two vegetarians is not merely a matter of preference-strength. Crucially, it is also a matter of intent. Their claims about vegetarianism will differ vis-à-vis intent, and the most proximate difference of intent is whether the prohibition applies only to themselves. Yet this matter of intent strikes me as being more fundamental than strength, for the greater strength of the one vegetarian's prohibition is presumably derived from the different quality of intent with which they give voice to their prohibition (and this would mean that intent is the more fundamental aspect). Granted, one might think that many vegetarians have conflated the strength of their prohibition with the scope of their prohibition, but I see no reason to assume that all vegetarians have made such a mistake.
Ok. So, I agree that there's a difference between the strength of a held preference and the breadth of a held preference (e.g., "this is my preference" and "this ought to be others' preference, or even if it's not, they ought to do it anyway"). The intents behind these are different, and important. I agree.
I think regardless of the breadth (whether I believe "I ought not to eat meat" or "
Nobody ought to eat meat"), the same sort of thing is going on, so I didn't think it was important to focus on that difference.
What I think is going on is that people have values from which they build oughts out of hypothetical imperatives: if I value x, then I ought to do y. In the case of breadth, the "y" that we do just includes "I ought to tell that guy over there to stop doing that." I think that we're only in charge of our own oughts, but the oughts we can come up with can include feeling like we ought to get others to go with our point of view (I can object to murder not because there's something about the universe that says murder is wrong, but because I value life, and since I value life, I ought to try to preserve it, and that includes telling someone else to knock off that murdering stuff they're trying to do; or putting them in prison so they can't do it any more!)
I think with breadth (when the ought "feels" like it applies to others and not just us), that is where the illusion of moral realism comes from. People feel like the ought is "out there" in the universe, and that the other people are subject to this ought "out there." But really, when we feel moral outrage, we are feeling our own hypothetical imperative to stop them from harming or interfering with what we value. If I value altruism and someone disgustingly rich doesn't even lift a finger to help the less fortunate, I feel outrage because they're harming my value, so I form the hypothetical imperative "if I value altruism, I ought to tell that guy what a cheapskate he is not to tip the waitress." It's not that reality really has an obligation on him to do so, and he obviously forms his own oughts with his own hypothetical imperatives stemming from his own values.
I feel like I haven't typed this very clearly. I worry that I'm unsure how to say what I'm trying to say, I'm somewhat multitasking right now. Perhaps if there's confusion I can come back later to take another stab at clarifying this.
Leontiskos wrote:So an implication of Good_Egg's observation seems to be that you are imputing an intent to the speaker of S1 that contradicts his own intent. That is, when he says that string cheese is tasty he is intending to speak about something beyond his preferences, and yet you have strangely circumscribed his speech to speech about preferences. If you agree with my analysis, then what do you think is going on here? Is the speaker of S1 hopelessly confused?
What I'm saying is more like this. I have seen people somewhat jokingly say about this or that thing, "I don't care what anyone says, [some subjective thing] is
objectively good." Maybe it's a song, a show, a piece of art, whatever. I get that most of the time people are joking. But I think that sometimes people make S1-type statements without irony because they're not paying attention to the philosophical ramifications of what it would mean. So in a sense, I think it is somewhat hopelessly confused if someone utters an S1-like statement. But my point isn't whether everybody does this or whether anybody does it often. My point is that we can probably all agree that S1 isn't propositional, yet it has the same form as S1a, which some people claim
is propositional, often without being able to elucidate why S1a is propositional yet S1 is not.