Re: On the nature of religion
Posted: December 9th, 2023, 8:32 pm
Count Lucanor wroteBut science has plenty to say about first person experience. It is not an accident that we can agree about the world. The question: is there a private language? generally looks to a person's observable language behavior as a social phenomenon, and even in the most private or idiosyncratic matters, it is the public language that is made, privately, available to the individual in her unshareable subjectivity. Another may not experience what I experience, but the language tht talks about it is not only public, but it constitutes the meanings that are spoken about.
If the issue was what it is like to be a cat, or your cat, in terms of their first person experience, there wouldn’t be much for science to say, but neither philosophy. Now, if the issue is what there is in the cat and in their relationship with other objects, what makes it an object within human experience, once the exteriority of objects, their ontic independence from the subject, as well as the exteriority of the bodily experience itself, has been acknowledged. For that, science and philosophy have many things to say.
And as far as ontic judgments, you have to be more clear. You know, Heidegger makes a rather important distinction between ontic and ontological matters, and this former term is what science and everydayness acknowledge. So if this ontic independence is meant to simply identify the preanalytic, preontological state of things, as is in the assumptions of everything from apples to astronomy, then phenomenology says you have reached the starting place of philosophy, the basic assumptions of a world that await critical work. BUT, for phenomenology, it will not be the same analytic themes, and this has been discussed often here. Science cares nothing for the presuppositional grounding of scientific axioms.
That demarcation line is highly disputable. What exactly we don’t need science for? Philosophy cannot say why after drinking alcohol I start tumbling. I saw a video of a cat doing that the other day. I certainly want to know why, what and how the cat is and I cannot longer do that without science. OK, you might want to speculate on what a cat means to a human, and you can say that’s a task reserved for the philosopher, but right off the bat he will have to take into account not only the manifest image of the cat and the world it lives, but the scientific image too, which inevitably has permeated society. I’m not saying either one or the other, but both, the synoptic view. What should I do with a cat? Why? Is it a guardian sent by the gods or just a simple mammal that showed up contingently? You have to know something about what the cat is and why it’s there. How do you do that, stepping out of the narratives of everyday living, without using the facts provided by science?That last part I understood. Not stepping on anyone's narratives. Phenomenology leaves everything in place, and does not for a moment violate one's sense of understanding the world through science. Phenomenology asks OTHER questions. The ones science ignores. For example, what is the structure of the conscious event that makes being drunk a conscious event? Consciousness is presupposed in drinking alcohol and tumbling around. You can't make a reference to brain states and their chemical analysis because such things as this presuppose a consciousness in the discussion of a chemical or the thought of a deviation from a norm. It is certainly NOT the case that talk about neurological imbalances is wrong. Phenomenology just doesn't talk about these things. I thought this clear. Look, just take this as an assumption: in any given area of science where a reasonable account is given, it is this accounts presuppositions that are phenomenology's interest. NOT the science claims at all.
I’m aware such phenomenologists are not mere Kant scholars, but do problematize on the legacy of the unsurpassable Kantian philosophy, to paraphrase Sartre, and have a tendency towards antirealism. Phenomenology needs not to be married to idealism, as the work of Merleau-Ponty demonstrates, so I don’t have a quarrel with phenomenology per se, but I do find problematic the doctrines of the “phenomenalist phenomenologists”. Add to that Kierkegaard’s theology and we have the recipe for disaster, the decadence of philosophy.Sartre is not going say that phenomenology CAN be married to realism in the sense that I think you are taking the word. Remember that Being and Nothingness BEGINS with a thesis of a phenomenological ontology. You can't say something like " Add to that Kierkegaard's theology and we have a recipe for disaster" and so forth as some disembodied generality that is clear for all to see. Only someone who has read Concluding Unscientific Postscripts, The Concept of Anxiety, Repetition, and so on can talk like this. You're way over your head to even mention the name. UNLESS, of course, you can actually argue the point. So do say, what disaster did you have in mind?
Phenomenology per se??? I guess you must be including Being and Time of the Cartesian Meditations, or Infinity and Totality.
Frankly, I don't care if you haven't read any of this. I never pursued the matter as if you had. I rather wanted to assume a physicalist or materialist body of assumptions and ask very innocently, how does epistemology work in the logic of this? This is what I led with, and it was simply an attempt to show that such attempt led very quickly to a reductio ad absurdum and the evidence for this was crystal clear: such a position simply has no epistemic function.
It is a premise that is massively simple. I think you resist for the entertainment of resisting. What other reason? Everyone knows this. Analytic philosophers know this. They got tired of talking about Kant because there was nothing left to talk about after a century of this. They didn't refute problem of "the legacy of the unsurpassable Kantian philosophy." But the French and the Germans didn't see things that way. They put Kant in bed with Hegel's historicity, Kierkegaards qualitative leap, Nietzsche's perspectivalism, and Husserl's epoche, and Heidegger's dasein, and on and on. And the philosophy hs only really come together in this very complicated legacy; but the irony of the legacy is this: the Husserlian reduction leads to only one thing, and that outstrips language itself!
It is not an easy thesis to defend as it already spells out its own reductio, and this is right up the alley of Wittgenstein's Tractatus which is famously disclaimed by Wittgenstein himself in the same work. Why does he do this? Because in this book he actually talks about matters that are both IN the fabric of meaning, yet outside of the logicality of language, and this is because, as I have said here and there, the metaphysics of old and the tiresome Christian apologetics, is reducible to the simplicity of givenness. One cannot speak of value, Witt insists, and therefore about ethics, because ethical/value good and bad are IN not reducible to other words that can be used to speak what these are.
I bring this up here because the massively simple question of epistemology undoes the metaphysics of science, scientific metaphysics, as I am calling it. The kind of claims that attempt make a move from premises derived from the naturalistic pov, to philosophy, as if, as Rorty put it, the brain were a mirror of nature. The idea is so patently absurd there is hardly room for it in a reasonable thought. Once metaphysics is freed from this kind of thing, one can start thinking as a phenomenologist (like Husserl, Heidegger, Levinas, Jen luc Nancy, Jean luc Marion, Derrida--a post modern phenomenologist. Not so much Merleau-Ponty, whom I have read little of, but what little I have...Even Rorty who straddles the fence): the ontological priorities are turned around, and value/ethics/aesthetics (you know Wittgenstein says ethics and aesthetics were essentially the same thing. I see why this is so: it is because value is the essence of both) are now, I argue, the very foundation of ontology.
This can be argued, but you first have to at least get to the admission that materialism flat out perishes in the epistemic reductio ad absurdum. It is the first step fo understanding the essence of religion, which is a metaethical problem, and Husserl's reduction take's one just there.
Alas, the reduction is less an argument than an orientation, a rerouting of what is privileged in meaning.
I’m not sure what you mean there. I’m not making a detailed analysis, that would take endless paragraphs, but I’m pointing to where the analysis has taken me. Surely we can make lots of sense of science claims about things apart from the perceiver’s contribution, such as things that existed before there was even any perceiver (the issue of ancestrality) and the fact of contingency.to look at this matter here, in the OP, one has to follow a certain path of reasoning. The point is this: It is IMPOSSIBLE to even begin to understand the "sense of science claims about things apart from the perceiver’s contribution." By your standards this sounds like a strong claim, and it is. But as I see it, you are conflating what is familiar and pragmatic with what survives an ontological critique. Science is a set of propositions and propositions are not over there among the bushes. What that over there is, sans the propositional knowledge, is an attempt to make a nonsense statement. I think Rorty and Wittgesntein are right (Rorty says this in Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, in a footnote on p 122). There are no quantifications over there IN something in the world. Easy enough to believe this about, say, color, for no onw actually believes the color green is literally "on" the leaf. Nor does the first year physiology student believe sounds exist without eardrums. This is too obvious to bother with.
Yet when I tell you that the thoughts in your head are not IN the world they are about, the prima facie objection should just as easily be dismissed. The reason you and I are so aligned with the world is not because we know the world as it IS in itself, but because we are equipped with strategies to deal with it. Knowledge is pragmatic, nothing more, says Rorty. But does this exhaust ontology? This is the question I wish to raise. I see the lamp on the table and ask what is the knowledge relation I have to this lamp? And this takes me to look at my own epistemic constitution, for I am the knower and am most intimate with this side of the relationship. So what does it mean to know?
The study of subjective structures goes way back, as you likely know, but the first real attempt that survives even today (see what I call a difficult book, Time and Narrative by Paul Ricoeur) is Augustine's in his Confessions. The knowledge "event" is temporal. To know about the lamp is to have already had lamp experiences, and so I always already know the lamp prior to the occasion. And AS I continue to observe the lamp, it continues to affirm all that I know in the recollection-anticipation of what it is. The present is a synthesis of past and future, and these are really never separate, because, in Heidegger's amazing examination, the past is only the past as I conceive of the past in an occurrent event that ITSELF is inherently anticipatory! I mean, ask me to think about yesterday pulling into the service station, and the recollection itself is actualized in the present moment of remembering, making the remembering an present, future looking event in real time.
This kind of thinking goes on and on in Heidegger. Husserl wrote a book on it, following Brentano, and I just bring it up to at least present how it is that a knowledge event is not beyond the conditions in which it occurs. This temporal structure of knowledge is categorically not over there up a tree or on my desk. tp speak in the straight physicalist terms of someone like Rorty. BUT: I do have an intimacy with trees and the rest that exceeds the mere pragmatic, the "taking care of issues" that arrive in my encounters with them. This is rather fascinating a question, for it cuts to the marrow of the question of being: the tree IS and I know this in a way that is not pragmatics. Heidegger called this presence at hand. Descartes referred to res extensa. Husserl called this, and I think he was right, a transcendental object made immanent by intentionality, which brings me to my point: how is it that anything out there gets in here? When I see my aunt, I am NOT looking at brain functions and I am NOT confined to the delimitations of idealism; she is NOT an idea.
But there is no way out of the phenomenon. We accept that my aunt is my aunt, but we have to accept the analytic of experience (or dasein or consciousness) as well. She is there, but conditioned by experience. But how do we avoid Wittgenstein's insistence that there is no "outside" of the logical grid that structures judgment? It must be that this "nexus of intentionality" that brings her into the contexts of meaning in me has a metaphysical dimension. My aunt, if you can stand this kind of talk, or even if you can't, stands at the threshold of my finitude as a transcendental entity that is received as a phenomenon, and Wittgenstein was simply wrong that we cannot talk about transcendence like this outside of they way language games sets up meaning possibilities because transcendence is not some impossible nonsense but rather "appears" IN the immanence of my aunt's being there.
Science is not philosophy, right, but science has philosophical foundations, which means every time science produces verifiable results, they have philosophical implications that cannot be simply dismissed by pure introspection. If science is not denied, its implicit realism and materialism cannot be denied either.Saying science has philosphical foundations is vague. And what is done here is not introspection. Introspection in the general sense is a reflection on one's own thoughts and feelings about something that occurs in the shared culture of living. Phenomenology is an apriori discovery of the structures of consciousness.
Philosophical foundations that are not revealed in science. This is the point. Husserl called his phenomenology a science, for his method was rigorous and objective. But his subject matter was not the world of empirical facts. It was about the presuppositional nature of those facts! Facts presuppose analysis, a meta-analysis, an analysis about the facts that are analyzed by science.
There’s no such inability, and ironically, it takes some presuppositions of philosophy to make such claim.Right, and that takes insight! This is Heidegger's view. No matter what is said, that being said is going to be hermeneutically grounded, The entirety of our finitude is based, not on the idea that there are objects in an independent world of physical dynamics, which cannot be made sense of at this level of inquiry, but on a pervasive indeterminacy. Quine admitted as much with his paper on translation (you know, the gavagi paper) and Derrida pissed everyone off by taking this hermeneutics to its only logical conclusion, which is a radical discontinuity between what can be said and what the world "is", this latter being necessarily a token of the former (because, heh, heh, I just said it). This is the first step into the extraordinary mystery of our existence. To see that our knowledge assumptions are about something that exists, and existence is only known in the encounters with existents or beingS (not being at all careful with these otherwise technical terms) and so the quest for the meaning at the basic level is to be found IN the analysis of the being of beings. This takes the analysis to the presuppositions of beings, the going to work, waiting for a bus, having dinner, paying taxes of being here, and well as the dogs and cats and fence posts, as well as set theory or cosmology. ALL of these are knowledge claims, and hence ontology claims (you can't know something if it isn't there), and so ontology has its object, but this, too, will be hermeneutically indeterminate. BUT: philosophy has now found its foundational grounding: our radical indeterminacy as discoverable in the apriori investigations of our everydayness.
This has a telos: is there anything that can be disclosed that, as Kierkegaard put it, stands as its own presupposition? This simply means, is there anything that is not contingent on the hermeneutical indeterminacy of language? Something that is stand alone what it is without the indeterminacy of the openness interpretation? Something that would be like God is God actually existed. I argue that there is such a thing, and this lies in metaethics, the essence of religion.
Science is portrayed here as if it was just a little more refined version of the naive inductive attitude of sense-making after first-hand impressions, which is sort of an inversion of what really happens: when it comes to thinking about how the world is, philosophical reflection has been for ages in a dark room making guesses. Science is not about ordinary life, it makes no use of ordinary language, and it is definitely not playing in the default setting, what one might call the manifest image. That’s why science has been able to revolutionize the common worldview that for ages depended on the kind of reflection inherent to religion and contemplative philosophy.When a phenomenologist refers to the naturalistic attitude, she is not referring to primitive notions of ancient paradigms. To understand what phenomenologists mean by this "default setting" requires one to actually participate. One has to "do" the phenomenological reduction, or what Kierkegaard called making a qualitative leap. I can't really help you here, for the reduction is a method that takes one into a novel perspective in which all the knoweldge claims that actively participate in perceiving the world are suspended, save those which are pure, to think like Husserl, or ontological, to think like Heidegger. The real issues of phenomenology really don't come alive until one does this, and to do this you have to practice it. How do you practice this method? Observe the world around you without the "always already there" assumptions that things are such and such and so and so and allow yourself to witness the world that has always been there but ignored.
So science is not denied its modern techniques nor the complex equational models. The point is that none of these achieves the reduction. One is not invited to "see" the models of perceptual possibility in science. Where does the reduction take one? This is what attracts inquiry into the nature of religion because to see what religion is, one has to penetrate through this ontic world you mentioned: the body of distractions, very helpful and useful distractions, granted, that cover phenomenological underpinnings and close understanding dogmatically. Ask, what is dogmatism? It is the authoritative pronouncement over something that is fixed and doesn't yield to objections. Science does not yield to the objections of phenomenology in the matter of ontology, and in this, it is the same as everydayness.
The phenomenon IS the witnessing of the event, the correlation between thinking and being, not what actually is, that is, the witnessed. Then there’s the question of whether both terms of the correlation are real, if they exist independently on their own, that is, if the event exists in a realm exterior to the phenomenal, witnessing world or not. Any phenomenologist denying that such exteriority can be affirmed, is denying science.But the actuality IS the event. Your are not in Parmenides' world, but in Heraclitus'. See the above painfully brief sketch of being-in-time.Such an object that is an actuality beyond thought and being, or becoming, has never been witnessed, and to think of it requires an act of inference from the temporal dynamic to something that is OUT of this dynamic and this requires one to step outside of experience itself. Thought itself IS an event. There is actually something quite profound in this, for the "event" is called as such IN the event of calling, naming, which attempts to still the event to immutability, as if in this event of observing this lamp, there is an element that stands apart from the event of understanding it, as if the "lampness" were somehow intimated. Sounds Platonic? Yes, very. And not an defensible position.
Both terms of the correlation? You refer to thinking and being? But these are one, for one cannot conceive of being without the thought of being. The moment being comes to mind, it is a particle of language.
Grrr. Phenomenology is not denying science. It is telling us that we have to have another set thesis in place, one thematically zoned in on ontology, when the discussion turns to things like knowledge relationships and existence and being.
Nope. Solipsism is strange to physicalism, it is a stance exclusive to idealism. When you deny the exteriority of objects, even the surface of your skull, you’re in for a ride on the slide to solipsism.But taking physicalism as the final say of the way we can describe the world makes the world itself impossible, because such a reduction would make all experience a physical object's internal affair. This is not, I am aware, what you intend, but the logic is clear: My consciousness is a brain event. This means every imaginable thing is just this; that is, unless you can show me a way out of the brain using the assumption of physicalism. That would be most welcome. But keep in mind that you would have to define the terms of physicalism that allow just this, and in doing so you would have to ad hoc include something that is extraneous to the concept. This is allowed, of course, but not under the name of physicalism.
“Conceiving” of exterior objects goes only to knowledge, how they appear in my experience, which we can all agree, without embracing the main currents of phenomenology, implies that our first-hand apprehension of reality is filtered by our senses, we can’t get all of it right away. But that does not say anything about the objects themselves and whether they actually exist on a realm (the physical world) that is contingent and not created by the conceiving mind. Once the exteriority of objects is acknowledged, including other subjects and other experiences which are not mine, realism takes in and there’s no escape back to denying their existence as objects and their relationships in themselves.There is a lot taken on in this, and I don't think it is easy because of the entangled nature of this weird area of inquiry.
Filtered? Can't really talk like this, can you? To say the object is filtered by the senses implies a knowledge of the unfiltered condition and this doesn't bear out of the analysis. It is certainly NOT that we don't have this IN our experience, but the understanding does not reach beyond the conditions of its own interpretative possibilities. This would be bad metaphysics. Not at all that it is unreasonable to affirm its independent existence, but to do so one once again encounters Wittgenstein: outside of the logical grid there is nothing to say, for all that can be said must be done logically, that is, conform to the basic categories similar to what Aristotle laid out. But then, how is it that to affirm what is not logical in nature becomes an issue. I know the lamp, but before me is a great deal that is not language, and I know this, too.
This is the threshold of thought. One encounters an indeterminacy. For religion and my purpose here, it is not the indeterminacy of affirming things like lamps and cats; it is the indeterminacy of our ethics that is where the argument begins.
As to the rest, it all rests on the assumption that one can have a meaningful conversation about things beyond the reach of language. Pure nonsense. This is not a denial of science, yet again, but a denial of this kind of scientific metaphysics.
Now, talk about breeding nonsense. That’s simply impossible, and such contradiction goes to show the absurdity of the phenomenologist views that you defend.Here is what you said:
1) to assume that this "reality" is entirely structured by his own mind. There's no point in investigating anything of it, because there's no knowable, intelligible world to start with, only the structure of the subject's own mind, the only mind that could exist. Since this reality appears as if talking back to him, as if it were independent, as if there were things outside of his experience, the structure of that mind can only make sense as hallucination, a dream at best. Or 2) To assume that this "reality" has a structure of its own, an intrinsic nature that is not only decodable, interpretable, intelligible, but that also requires the participation of other subjects to figure out how it works, by contributing with the telling of their own knowledge and experiences. This second attitude is the only one that allows for the establishment of philosophy and science, it's the only one that allows the world to be intelligible.You're missing the point. The idea is to take all that one knows and allow it. Nothing is missing from science in a phenomenologist's take on things, for since it is essentially bound to descriptive inclusiveness, then the entire appearance is preserved, and space is still what NASA says it is, and time is still about when class begins. Only phenomenology insists that what holds for the ontic world of affairs is not complete in the most basic analysis because things are very different in the presuppositional analysis. This should be a familiar method as science does this all the time. We participate in the world unreflectively in many ways, but ask a physicist, say, to give a more detailed examination of my car's molecular composition, and it will be forth coming. Both are true, it being a car that I drive to work AND the molecular description. The latter does not cancel the former. So how can two (or many more, really) descriptive accounts of the same thing be true yet radically divergent? Where is the real "thing"? 'Clearly the interpretation of the that object is variable; it depends on the perspective.
Phenomenology is saying just this: Look at the world phenomenologically, and the descriptive terms are very different, though science sustains as well. Phenomenology is a foundational ontology, however, and so analysis can go no further. Husserl holds the intuitive givenness to be an absolute, and while this is hard defend his basic justification lies in the simplicity of the insistence that SOMETHING there is not hermeneutical, but just bare presence. Heidegger's is more appreciated: the car, the molecular composition, the phenomenlogical analysis are all mutually sustainable.