Count Lucanor wrote
But I wonder, who has suggested that ontology can be disentangled from the very cognition that conceives it? What's your point there? I have made statements that promote the view that ontology and epistemology are a unity within philosophy. What I have rejected is the supremacy of epistemology, which makes ontology its subordinate or dismisses it altogether.
Not that it makes it subordinate. It simply sees ontology to be inextricably bound to claims about what is, in the "essence" of ontology, if you will, such that no analysis of what IS at the most basic level (philosophy) can ignore what IS there that constitutes the relation of 'S knows P' between S and P. The "being" of this knowing is one thing Husserl is essentially about. You can't treat S as if it simply a given object like P. Nor is the matter to be taken as a simple flaw or incongruity in standard thinking about objects that exists between S and P, for this assumes there is some basis for describing the incongruity. The point is that one cannot even imagine how the being of my cat can be known in the basic scientific paradigms of what relationships are between objects. I mean, relationships between objects: this is paramount in the way science does business.
This is why we need something that is not confined to scientific paradigms to discuss this.
Sure, but Heidegger stands on the shoulders of the idealists that came before him. When he tackles ontology, it already implies the phenomenical approach that started with Kant and was endorsed by Husserl. Heidegger is then more interested in the meaning of being, rather than in being itself. Dasein is the epistemological being, the being that knows "being there".
Not Kant. Remember that Heidegger's thinking was about human existence not the form of judgments, making him a philosopher of existence. This is why such notions and caring and death and Kierkegaard's concept of anxiety and the nothingness one faces when one is released from existent
iell interpretative perspectives are front and center. The whole of dasein is a radical finitude! And the noumenality of transcendence is replaced by a yielding to the world, which he talks about using the term gelassenheit, an "allowing" the world to speak as one withdraws the "will" of one's totality, which means one stops trying to insist on the way the world should be and yields to what is tells us through the possibilities afforded by finitude, which are inherently hermeneutical and historical.
Heidegger's world is very complicated, as he at once constructs his own pov out of the very ones who he critiques so severely. He is no Cartesian, or Kantian, of Husserlian or Kierkegaardian or Nietzschean thinker grounded especially in the Greeks and the pre-Socratics. Rather he takes all of these into an entirely new philosophy. Breathtaking to read, really. It is not the nexus of intentionality that is Husserl's contribution that he elucidates. He does not use the term consciousness, but dasein: our existence thrown into a world in foundational indeterminacy. But to see this one has to go through the standard texts of Kant, Hegel and the rest (there are so many), in order to step out of the narratives of everyday living. No, not epistemology, but an ontology that IS the epistemology. Take Time. Not exactly an epistemological term, but descriptive of the event that unfolds before me in the most basic analysis of our existence when I observe my couch or the fine day outside. What is, in the view of science, a horizon of physical objects (and their massively complex constitutions and quantified values) is put under the apriori analysis: I see the couch, but when I see it, I already know it, that is, it does not surprise me with its being there, but on the contrary, is comfortably acknowledged. Science would dismiss this. Of course, it admits talk about short term and long term memory, neurology, and so forth, but, and this important: all of these accounts in science presuppose the consciousness that conceives them. Phenomenology asks the most basic questions about the structure of this primordial givenness. To talk about, in other words, what memory is, we are already deploying memory; memory is presupposed by this psychology discussion about memory, so is there a way to discuss memory at this level of presuppositions? This requires an apriori investigation, not an empirical one. Apriority here means asking what must be the case to explain what is there in the original everydayness. Kant's method, but taken to its furthest reaches, the whole of our dasein. Husserl, following Brentano, inquires about time and we instantly see that we are miles away from anything science can say. This is not Einstein's time, but what is presupposed by Einstein: internal time (so called by Husserl).
This has to be read to be understood, but it is not trying to say how objects are known, though this is intimately involved, but what they are, and they are in time in the preapprehension of the encounter, and the anticipation that is a unity of the recollection as one does not anticipate without remembering, and ...well, it is a fascinating read. I would just remind that this is a process of extrapolation, analysis of what is the case clearly, like the features of time, its past, present and furture, to what must be the case as a presupposition, not at all alien to science.
This is pure Husserl's phenomenological reduction, I guess. It pretends to destroy the distinction between object and consciousness of objects, concerned as he is only with "a theory of knowledge", which of course rests heavily on the doctrine that mind structures reality. The great enemy has to be science, to which Husserl directs his critiques in the form of disputes against the underlying psychological assumptions of perception and subsequent logical rationalizations. The problem is: there's more than this in scientific endeavors, so, the "purely philosophical" position that Husserl takes implies total rejection of science, or better said, the implied realism in science. Bhaskar, along with other modern realists, was crystal-clear about the incompatibilty between science and epistemic correlationism: objects must be completely independent of humans for scientific practice to be intelligible. That makes Husserl's position, which still pretends to leave its legitimacy untouched, absurd. The reason for this, obviously, is that he is really after naturalism, because...well, we know where that is going.
Well...grrr. Please note that all of this talk about destroying distinctions and attacking science and epistemic correlationism possesses not one iota of analysis. Just vague generalities. What ever happened to: Can you even begin to make sense of science's knowledge claims apart from the perceiver's contribution? I'm listening...
It is not that there is no truth in this above here, but these would be partial truths at best. Phenomenology doesn't deny science. It denies that science is foundational philosophy. I would think this to be crystal clear.
Phenomenlogy simply wants to talk about the presuppositions of science. It wants to discuss the internal temporality of knowledge claims, the apperceptive nature of knowing, the inability to extricate material objects from conscious events, the pragmatic nature knowing contra presence of things, the relationship between universals and particulars and how the latter can at all be affirmed for what it is given how knowledge claims deal in universals, hermeneutical openness vis a vis the scientific paradigms of normal science; and on and on. These things don't interest a scientist, but they are implicit in every claim she makes. This is why we have philosophy.
It's actually the opposite: it is for phenomenologists that things don't make make prima facie sense, so they quit. But a realism supported by science is not prima facie, it goes to justification, right, but it's a lenghty road to get there, besides requiring going back and forth, systematically.
Think of something prima facie here as a kind of default setting of the way we experience and think about the world. The mail comes, dinner's ready, time for school, etc., and in this setting there are assumptions in place about what the world is. There indeed ARE letters, dinners, and of course, particle physicists and and neuroanatomists. Everything in this default setting of our existence, is epistemically defeasible, to use their jargon, which means any given proposition is "defeatable" and not absolute. Of course, you are right to say that science steps apart from this everydayness to make more disciplined discoveries, but it remains mostly true to what Husserl calls the naturlalistic attitude, which is stated clearly in, Quine's, "Philosophically I am bound to Dewey by the naturalism that dominated his last three decades. With Dewey I hold that knowledge, mind, and meaning are part of the same world that they have to do with, and that they are to be studied in the same empirical spirit that animates natural science. There is no place for a prior philosophy." I don't know if I mentioned this earlier, but I do like its conciseness. This is the kind of thing Husserl and others (they are all different and generalizations almost instantly fail) think is wrong minded, for the very reasons I went over above: it goes absolutely nowhere because it stays with the default setting of nature-as-we-know-it, science and ordinary language. Best example I can think of is Dennett's Consciousness Explained, a reduction of philosophical issues, and all issues, really, to brain talk. I would point out that nearly every argument Dennett brings to bear upon phenomenology is a pseudo argument. He tells us that the "ineffability" of hearing a musical sound can be explained, at least in part by a discussion about guitar strings' tonalities sounding together in one way or anpother. Question: does Dennett even once address the questions underscored in, say, Heidegger's Being and time? No. Look, the simple truth is philosophers like this, naturalistic ones< if you will, simply do not want to think about question like that! It is certainyy not that they have some kind of grasp in these ancient philosophical issues; they are simply dismissive because they are utterly committed to the default setting of normal science, as Kuhn put it.
The one thing that boils my noodle about Dennett is that he says outright, mocks deirectly, the objection that physicalism can never touch, come within miles of, the bottom line thoughts and palpable encounters in the world, all the while not giving the slightest care that his own argumentative logic and observations are exactly this! He will not admit that "semantical and intentional phenomena cannot be incorporated within the science of nature" while all along the very essence of the thought that constructs his thesis are semantical and intentional phenomena!!
But, speaking of Kuhn, there is a "revolutionary" step forward one can take. When do revolutions occur in science? When there is an intractable anomaly. What is the intractable anomaly that phenomenology addresses? It is the indisputable phenomenological nature of experience that cannot be witnessed in Dennett's physical reductionist terms. E.g., how does the finding of a brain event of my cat in some objective, measurable way: bridge the epistemic distance between the thought and the cat? Escape the confines of physicality's profound limits in accounting for meaning, intentions, logic and semiotics and its semantics, value and caring; and generally speaking, the phenomenological presuppositions of what anything physical could be? How does it deal with the structures that are inherent IN the observational event?? Rorty said it: the brain is not a mirror, and one has to look deeply into this.
IF a physical or naturalist reduction is the final word, then it is literally impossible to have a thought "about" something that is not the thought itself. This IS Rorty's position. Truth is made not discovered. He though Heidegger to be one of the three greatest philosopher's of the 20th century. I certainly don't agree with his nihilism, which he denies, or tries to, but you see, he sides with Quine and Dewey,
NOT because he believes science understands the world at the most basic level of analysis (he is a pragmatist), but because he has taken an honest look at the physicalist claims and realized that this world really is contained within such an overwhelming finitude, something that will simply not be outstripped, and this means, for him, the very end of the meaning of the term metaphysics. Odd to think that he is following the analytic strain of Kantianism, which is the impossibility of metaphysics.
But again, undermining science, its very nature itself, including its necessary realism, has the implication that we are simply hallucinating. The phenomenalist workaround for this is simply absurd.
Not hallucinating, simply because phenomenology, being essentially descriptive, of course recognizes the differences between hallucinations and objective actualities. Both are actual! Which is to say, a hallucination is not nothing at all, and its locality within a brain event is still a locality (though brain events themselves are phenomena), but it has certain descriptive features that set it apart from facts about the objective (public) world.
Science is NEVER undermined! Scientific metaphysics, well, that is quite another thing. Again, the only thing anyone has every witnessed is the phenomenon. It is IMPOSSIBLE to witness anything else, for to witness at all is a phenomenological event. Facts like this are hard for the Dennett's of the world to accept, which is why he ignores them. Phenomenologists accept a great deal of what he says when he talks about physics and other sciences, but they simply respond, but you haven't taken the matters of the world to the most basic level.
Truly, I probably don't disagree with ninety nine percent of everything you believe. I simply say to go all the way, one has to deal with phenomenology. Philosophy takes us to the limits of our understanding; this is its point.
But Heidegger means "being" as a verb, as the experience of being, the meaning of it, not as the thing that actually is. It's all about the notion of not having access, but that's an ontological claim, which as you said, requires justification. When you look at Husserl's and Heidegger's justifications, they are disputable, and they have been disputed.
Do tell. Let the analysis itself be your guide, not hearsay. IN order to affirm something that is not an event but is a permanent fixed entity beyond the event of of perceiving, one would have to actually witness such a beyondness to even make sense of the term. What to we say about things that are beyond experience? We call them metaphysical. Yes, scientific foundationalism is just bad metaphysics. Not that it has never been observed; rather, it cannot be observed unless you completely change what we mean by the term 'observe'. Phenomenology makes just this move.
I borrow from Ryle's vocabulary: thinking science to be a philosophically foundational is a "category mistake". Science simply does not deal in the thematic areas that are the principle focus of phenomenology. Those who dispute this are mostly those who don't read phenomenology. Or scientists like Dennett who read but don't understand.
Yes, that's just the same as dismissing science altogether. Husserl goes directly against science, it's a key philosophical and foundational issue for him, not just another theme. Either apples or oranges, if you go for oranges, apples are out of the picture. They are not "recontextualized" oranges.
Dismissing science in the way mentioned above, yes. In no other way, though. Husserl goes directly against science VIS A VIS claims that exceed science's purview. Just that .
If it helps, you can think of it as human-independent. Not the telling, which has to be human, but that which is pointed at as actually existing, objectively, as a thing in itself, independently of the human in itself.
Then you are going to have to deal with our own terms. Human-independent? Obviously there are things that are not me. All that there is to do is describe what is there. No way to disentangle that couch from the perceptual act, so the couch remains over there, apart from me, yet a phenomenon (and we all know the history on this entanglement: is there heaviness in the couch? How about color? Or smell? How do the couch's measurements and the apodicticity of their logicality belong to the couch? And naming, referring to it as a couch, this certainly doesn't belong to the couch, nor do the quantifications of intensities that describe its physical binding...I mean the knowledge that we have, that a scientist has of the object is all intricately bound to the apriority of the in the features of its existence. This is Kant, essentially. You can make a traditional move to calling these features either primary or secondary, the former being in space and time, but really?: time is outside of the perceiver? What about the presupposition of this that deals with internal time of the perceptual event?
How many knowledge claims about the world are possible that are NOT inherent claims about the perceptual apparatus that receives them? None. Obviously we talk as if they are free of such things, but this has been a pragmatic assumption, we talk simply and with general purpose, just as when we talk about shells on the beach we generally don't talk about the sciences about them.
Not exactly the same thing. The phenomenalists are looking for the universal, unchanging, non-historical essences, supposedly deduced from the simple contemplative efforts of idealist philosophy. The real, the concrete, appears as completely accesory, almost a hallucination, a byproduct of
the belief in having access to noumena.
No, this is completely wrong. And in truth, it's so wrong that I see that I cannot even begin to right this. It would take pages. Phenomenology varies in its ideas. Alas, one does have to read enough of it to see how it all works. Universal non changing essences? Husserl but certainly not Heidegger, nor Levinas, nor any post modern, post Heideggerian thinking. Simple contemplative efforts of idealist philosophy? Please note how free of content this is. How could I respond if you don't tell me what you mean by it? Argue something. This is like saying nothing at all. The real and concrete? This is all phenomenology is interested in. Unless you can explain how the real is to be pried loose from the phenomenon.
But if everything is a construct, it is someone's construct, and that construction includes the other beings that appear to construct within that someone's construction. The phenomenological totality shows other human beings as phenomena and as such they don't get justified in their real existence, mere nomenclature that does not justify either to talk about "we" or "they". Phenomenology ends up, just the same as all its philosophical predecessors, in solipsism.
Solipsism occurs, and this is important, only when one weds physicalism with idealism, as if idealism contained experience within the shell of a skull. Please review the many times I explained why this is not the case. Phenomenology clearly acknowledges the exteriority of objects. It simply tells us that these objects cannot be conceived apart from the conceiving. Any attempt to do so would be self refuting. Try it.
That's just an example of the search for the universal, unchanging, non-historical essences behind the objects of experience, which is, interestingly, a sort of realism, but an unjustified realism, supported only by a purely contemplative and incoherent philosophical reflection that crashes with its own doctrines. Since those objects are not concrete actualities, but pure constructions of a mind, what would be the point of talking about the social as real, or religion as a real practice of real subjects? It would be the essence of what exactly? What is meant by "our existence"? Isn't it the world too, that which we cannot speak? It is there, sure, but what justifies religion being there that is not included within the justification itself? The essence becomes another construction and you end up with nothing but the construction, without this having any foundation.
Nonhistorical? you do know that Heidegger's phenomenology is explicitly historical. You do know that hermeneutics is explicitly historical. No, not pure constructions of a mind. This is why you and others find yourselves arguing with yourselves.
Knowledge relationships? OK, it's fun. Regardless of the nature or "essence" of the world and that which "knows", I mean, with independence of having a realist or antirealist philosophical stance, it cannot be disputed that there's something that knows, the subject, and something that is known, the objects or contents of our experience. Now, if you want to dispute that, I'm all ears.
I do take issue with calling the subject a thing. I do a once over on myself and find many things, but no objects. That lamp is an object. Me? I am thinking, feeling, intending, liking, disliking, agreeing, offended, and so on. It is indicative of the way your perspective has been influenced by physicalist reductive thinking. You see how this breeds nonsense.
To say that "there is something", that an object "is there", means that it exists, which could be just the same as saying "the subject has the experience" of that thing that is claimed to be there, without any commitment to a "thing in itself".
Did you just say the object being there is the same thing as the subject having the experience of the thing (putting "thing in itself" talk aside)?
So, right off the bat, we have the knower, the known and the knowing, all as experience, all as existent, all being there. That's the basic template, which does not clash with a phenomenological approach. Now, we can begin to look at some interesting things that show up within the experience: the known includes the objects that appear exerting influence and determining other objects. It also includes other knowers and other knowing from their part, which also implies that the knower is known back, and that the knowers are, at the same time, the known. All of this constitute what we may call "the world" that the subject experiences. But there's something else: the knowers are not mute, they utter (or at least appear to utter) their knowledge of the knowers, the known and the knowing. The content of these utterances implies that there are other experiences, other knowledge, that is independent of our own and to which we have no access to. Now, there are only two attitudes that the subject can adopt when facing this "world", as it appears configured before his eyes: 1) to assume that this "reality" is entirely structured by his own mind. There's no point in investigating anything of it, because there's no knowable, intelligible world to start with, only the structure of the subject's own mind, the only mind that could exist. Since this reality appears as if talking back to him, as if it were independent, as if there were things outside of his experience, the structure of that mind can only make sense as hallucination, a dream at best. Or 2) To assume that this "reality" has a structure of its own, an intrinsic nature that is not only decodable, interpretable, intelligible, but that also requires the participation of other subjects to figure out how it works, by contributing with the telling of their own knowledge and experiences. This second attitude is the only one that allows for the establishment of philosophy and science, it's the only one that allows the world to be intelligible.
Phenomenology subsumes both 1 and 2.