Consul wrote: ↑March 31st, 2022, 3:09 pmBelindi wrote: ↑March 31st, 2022, 4:50 am
Consul wrote: ↑March 30th, 2022, 4:30 pmAnyway, a subjectless subjective idealism cannot be true, because it is ontologically incoherent.
That's right. That is why I like absolute idealism where there are no objects or subjects but experience only. (See Bradley)
In particular, Bradley rejected on these grounds the view that reality can be understood as consisting of many objects existing independently of each other (pluralism) and of our experience of them (realism). Consistently, his own view combined substance monism — the claim that reality is one, that there are no real separate things — with metaphysical idealism — the claim that reality consists solely of idea or experience. This vision of the world had a profound effect on the verse of T.S. Eliot, who studied philosophy at Harvard and wrote a Ph.D. thesis on Bradley.
(Stanford Dictionary of Philosophy)
Absolute idealism isn't a subjectless subjective idealism, so I doubt that Bradley's claim really is "that reality consists solely of idea or experience." – I'll check it!
Okay, Bradley's absolute idealism is different from Hegel's, and Bradley does believe in absolute, i.e.
subjectless, experience—
incoherently, I'm afraid!
Experience (in the phenomenological sense) is
subjective experience; so where there is experience, there is subjectivity. But there cannot be any (mental) subjectivity without any (mental) subjects: Experiences cannot be
non-experienced by anything and they cannot be
self-experiencing either, so there must be
experiencing subjects which aren't experiences themselves. This is a necessary truth following from the essence of (subjective) experience!
Bradley writes that "everything is experience"; but if nothing is nonexperience, with subjects of experience being nonexperiences, then nothing is experience either. For experiences depend for their being on the being of those nonexperiences which are
experiencers (experiencing subjects).
QUOTE>
"We perceive, on reflection, that to be real, or even, barely to exist, must be to fall within sentience. Sentient experience, in short, is reality, and what is not this is not real. We may say, in other words, that there is no being or fact outside of that which is commonly called psychical existence. Feeling, thought, and volition (any groups under which we class psychical phenomena) are all the material of existence, and there is no other material, actual or even possible. This result in its general form seems evident at once; and, however serious a step we now seem to have taken, there would be no advantage at this point in discussing it at length. For the test in the main lies ready to our hand, and the decision rests on the manner in which it is applied. I will state the case briefly thus. Find any piece of existence, take up anything that any one could possibly call a fact, or could in any sense assert to have being, and then judge if it does not consist in sentient experience. Try to discover any sense in which you can still continue to speak of it, when all perception and feeling have been removed; or point out any fragment of its matter, any aspect of its being, which is not derived from and is not still relative to this source. When the experiment is made strictly, I can myself conceive of nothing else than the experienced. Anything, in no sense felt or perceived, becomes to me quite unmeaning. And as I cannot try to think of it without realizing either that I am not thinking at all, or that I am thinking of it against my will as being experienced, I am driven to the conclusion that for me experience is the same as reality. The fact that falls elsewhere seems, in my mind, to be a mere word and a failure, or else an attempt at self-contradiction. It is a vicious abstraction whose existence is meaningless nonsense, and is therefore not possible.
This conclusion is open, of course, to grave objection, and must in its consequences give rise to serious difficulties. I will not attempt to anticipate the discussion of these, but before passing on, will try to obviate a dangerous mistake. For, in asserting that the real is nothing but experience, I may be understood to endorse a common error. I may be taken first to divide the percipient subject from the universe; and then, resting on that subject, as on a thing actual by itself, I may be supposed to urge that it cannot transcend its own states. Such an argument would lead to impossible results, and would stand on a foundation of faulty abstraction. To set up the subject as real independently of the whole, and to make the whole into experience in the sense of an adjective of that subject, seems to me indefensible. And when I contend that reality must be sentient, my conclusion almost consists in the denial of this fundamental error. For if, seeking for reality, we go to experience, what we certainly do
not find is a subject or an object, or indeed any other thing whatever, standing separate and on its own bottom. What we discover rather is a whole in which distinctions can be made, but in which divisions do not exist. And this is the point on which I insist, and it is the very ground on which I stand, when I urge that reality is sentient experience. I mean that to be real is to be indissolubly one thing with sentience . It is to be something which comes as a feature and aspect within one whole of feeling, something which, except as an integral element of such sentience, has no meaning at all. And what I repudiate is the separation of feeling from the felt, or of the desired from desire, or of what is thought from thinking, or the division—I might add—of anything from anything else. Nothing is ever so presented as real by itself, or can be argued so to exist without demonstrable fallacy. And in asserting that the reality is experience, I rest throughout on this foundation. You cannot find fact unless in unity with sentience, and one cannot in the end be divided from the other, either actually or in idea. But to be utterly indivisible from feeling or perception, to be an integral element in a whole which is experienced, this surely is itself to
be experience. Being and reality are, in brief, one thing with sentience: they can neither be opposed to, nor even in the end distinguished from it.
I am well aware that this statement stands in need of explanation and defence. This will, I hope, be supplied by succeeding chapters, and I think it better for the present to attempt to go forward. Our conclusion, so far, will be this, that the Absolute is one system, and that its contents are nothing but sentient experience. It will hence be a single and all-inclusive experience, which embraces every partial diversity in concord. For it cannot be less than appearance, and hence no feeling or thought, of any kind, can fall outside its limits. And if it is more than any feeling or thought which we know, it must still remain more of the same nature. It cannot pass into another region beyond what falls under the general head of sentience. For to assert that possibility would be in the end to use words without a meaning. We can entertain no such suggestion except as self-contradictory, and as therefore impossible."
(pp. 127-9)
"There is but one Reality, and its being consists in experience. In this one whole all appearances come together, and in coming together they in various degrees lose their distinctive natures. The essence of reality lies in the union and agreement of existence and content, and, on the other side, appearance consists in the discrepancy between these two aspects. And reality in the end belongs to nothing but the single Real."
(p. 403)
"Everything is experience, and also experience is one."
(p. 404)
"Reality then is one, and it is experience. It is not merely
my experience, nor again can we say that it consists of souls or selves."
(p. 469)
(Bradley, F. H.
Appearance and Reality. 1897 [2nd ed.]. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930 [9th impr.].)
<QUOTE
——————
QUOTE>
"Absolute reality lies beyond any distinction between subject and object, or self and not-self. Yet how, if there are no experiencing selves, can anything, let alone everything, be experienced? The impossibility of conceiving anything that is not experienced is surely one with the impossibility of conceiving anything that is not experienced by someone, by some subject.
It is to be noted that Bradley himself does not present his conclusion as saying that everything must be
experienced; rather he says that everything is
experience or
sentience itself. Presumably this formulation is supposed to bring out the fact that the sentience of the Absolute is not that of some experiencing self. But the change of words hardly helps us. While we think of the claim as the conclusion of some quasi-Berkelian line of reasoning, it still seems to involve a subject or self, in at least some minimal sense of these terms; but, if we think of the conclusion as characterizing something wholly beyond any distinction between subject and object, it is hard to see it as the appropriate conclusion of the argument under consideration, for that argument operates at the level of ordinary experience which is subject-object in structure.
(Mander, W. J.
An Introduction to Bradley's Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. p. 131)
———
According to Bradley…
"Reality is somehow one vast eternal self-experiencing many-in-one."
("Bradley, F. H.", by T. L. S. Sprigge. In
The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, 2nd ed., edited by Ted Honderich. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. p. 105)
———
"[O]ne has to consider Bradley’s treatment of the notion of the self. In his view, there cannot be a subject without an object. Since self and not-self, subject and object, are correlative and can’t therefore be divorced from one another, they form a relational structure that, as such, can only develop within the larger whole of feeling. The self is, as Bradley says, ‘one of the results gained by transcending the first . . . form of experience’ (AR 525). But
whose experience, then, is immediate experience? Bradley answers this question in terms of the notion of a finite centre. This is to be viewed as the
metaphysical point in which all of a person’s experiences unfold. However, such a centre is neither a self (as we have just seen) nor can it properly be called a ‘soul’ (AR 529), for according to Bradley a soul’s life must be capable of enduring for a significant amount of time, while the experiences unfolding within a finite centre might be as brief as a momentary occurrence, breaking into existence, as it were, like a light flashing in the dark. Bradley also thinks that finite centres are not
themselves in time, although there obviously is a temporal quality to the experiences unfolding within them. Most importantly, and puzzling as it might seem on a first hearing, Bradley denies that a finite centre is in any deep metaphysical sense a reality
distinct from its experiences. There is nothing more to the centre than the stream of its experiences—each is a quantum of flowing feeling."
(Basile, Pierfrancesco. "Bradley's Metaphysics." In
The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century, edited by W. J. Mander, 189-208. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. p. 203)
<QUOTE