* Keith Frankish:
Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness (PDF)
*
Illusionism about Qualia
*
The Illusionist Movement
QUOTE>
"It is not easy to persuade people to take illusionism seriously. In part, this is because it is easily caricatured as denying that we have sensations in the everyday sense (it would be more accurate to say that it rejects a certain conception of what sensations are)."
(Frankish, Keith. Editorial Introduction to
Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness. In
Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness, edited by Keith Frankish, 9-10. Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2017. p. 9)
———
"According to illusionists, our sense that it is like something to undergo conscious experiences is due to the fact that we systematically misrepresent them (or, on some versions, their objects) as having phenomenal properties. "
(p. 11)
"I propose ‘illusionism’ as a more accurate and inclusive name, and I shall refer to the problem of explaining why experiences seem to have phenomenal properties as the
illusion problem."
(p. 12)
"I shall use ‘phenomenal properties’, and, for variation, ‘phenomenal feels’ and ‘phenomenal character’, and I shall say that experiences with such properties are
phenomenally conscious.
(I shall use the term 'experience' itself in a functional sense, for the mental states that are the direct output of sensory systems. In this sense it is not definitional that experiences are phenomenally conscious.)"
(p. 13)
"Illusionists deny that experiences have phenomenal properties and focus on explaining why they seem to have them."
(p. 14)
"Illusionism makes a very strong claim: it claims that phenomenal consciousness is illusory; experiences do not really have qualitative, ‘what-it’s-like’ properties, whether physical or non-physical."
(p. 15)
"A quasi-phenomenal property is a non-phenomenal, physical property (perhaps a complex, gerrymandered one) that introspection typically misrepresents as phenomenal. For example, quasi-phenomenal redness is the physical property that typically triggers introspective representations of phenomenal redness. There is nothing phenomenal about such properties—nothing 'feely' or qualitative—and they present no special explanatory problem. Strong illusionists hold that the introspectable properties of experience are merely quasi-phenomenal ones."
(p. 15)
"I characterized illusionism as the view that phenomenal consciousness is an
introspective illusion[.]"
(p. 19)
"Does illusionism entail eliminativism about consciousness? Is the illusionist claiming that we are mistaken in thinking we have conscious experiences? It depends on what we mean by 'conscious experiences'. If we mean experiences with phenomenal properties, then illusionists do indeed deny that such things exist. But if we mean experiences of the kind that philosophers
characterize as having phenomenal properties, then illusionists do not deny their existence. They simply offer a different account of their nature, characterizing them as having mere quasi-phenomenal properties. Similarly, illusionists deny the existence of phenomenal consciousness properly so-called, but do not deny the existence of a form of consciousness (perhaps distinct from other kinds, such as access consciousness) which consists in the possession of states with quasi-phenomenal properties and is commonly mischaracterized as phenomenal. Henceforth, I shall use 'consciousness' and 'conscious experience' without qualification in an inclusive sense to refer to states that might turn out to be either genuinely phenomenal or only quasi-phenomenal. In this sense realists and illusionists agree that consciousness exists."
(p. 21)
"Are illusionists claiming that we are (phenomenal) zombies? If the only thing zombies lack is phenomenal consciousness properly so called, then illusionists must say that, in this technical sense, we are zombies. However, zombies are presented as creatures very different from ourselves—ones with no inner life, whose experience is completely blindsighted. As Chalmers puts it, 'There is nothing it is like to be a zombie…all is dark inside' (Chalmers, 1996, pp. 95-6). And illusionists will not agree that this is a good description of us. Rather, they will deny the equivalence between having an inner life and having phenomenal consciousness. Having the kind of inner life we have, they will say, consists in having a form of introspective self-awareness that creates the illusion of a rich phenomenology.
But aren't phenomenal properties precisely what makes experience
like something? That is certainly a common way of construing what-it's-like talk, but there is another way. Illusionists can say that one's experiences are like something if one is aware of them in a functional sense, courtesy of introspective representational mechanisms. Indeed, this is a plausible reading of the phrase; experiences are like something for a creature, just as external objects are like something for it, if it mentally represents them to itself. Illusionists agree that experiences are like something in this sense, though they add that the representations are non-veridical, misrepresenting experiences as having phenomenal properties. (what-it's-like-ness in the first sense). And in this second sense there
is something it is like to be a zombie, since zombies have introspective mechanisms functionally identical to our own. When we imagine zombies as being different from us, we are—illegitimately—imagining creatures with different introspective capacities."
(pp. 22-3)
"This brings us back to talk of it being
like something| to be us. As noted earlier, such talk may mean simply that we have an introspective awareness of our experiences, generated by representational mechanisms. We might call this
introspective subjectivity. Illusionists agree that we have introspective subjectivity, though they hold that it is radically misleading. But 'like something' talk can be understood in a stronger sense, as indicating that we possess a subjective dimension that is not a product of introspective mechanisms but arises simply from our being the things we are. Call this
intrinsic subjectivity."
(p. 31)
(Frankish, Keith. "Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness." In
Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness, edited by Keith Frankish, 11-39. Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2017.)
———
"The explanandum is the thing we call 'conscious experience', where it is an open question whether this involves phenomenality or the illusion of it."
(p. 257)
"[W]e can employ an inclusive concept of consciousness that does not carry a commitment to phenomenal realism and allows us to affirm the reality and significance of consciousness in a natural way."
(p. 274)
"There's no point mincing words: we don't have phenomenal properties, only representations of them."
(p. 274)
"[Schwitzgebel's] definition is so innocent, it is not incompatible with illusionism. As I stressed in the target article, illusionists do not deny the existence of the mental states we
describe as phenomenally conscious, nor do they deny that we can introspectively recognize these states when they occur in us. Moreover, they can accept that these states share some unifying feature. But they add that this feature is not possession of phenomenal properties (qualia, what-it’s-like-ness, etc.) in the substantive sense created by the phenomenality language game. Rather, it is possession of introspectable properties that dispose us to judge that the states possess phenomenal properties in that substantive sense (of course, we could call this feature phenomenality’ if we want, but I take it that phenomenal realists will not want to do that). "
(p. 277)
"Martine Nida-Rümelin begins her commentary by rejecting the widely held view that phenomenal consciousness consists in having experiences with phenomenal properties. Talk of experiences having phenomenal properties is, she argues, a confused way of talking about
subjects having
experiential properties, where these are properties that it is like something to undergo. If this is correct, then it immediately undercuts illusionism as originally presented. If it is confused to think that being phenomenally conscious involves having experiences with phenomenal properties, then it is equally confused to think that it involves having experiences that are misrepresented as having phenomenal properties. However, as Nida-Riimelin notes, illusionists may simply recast their view as the claim that we misrepresent ourselves as having experiential properties, and she goes on to argue against this claim."
(p. 286)
"Nida-Rümelins main argument appeals to facts about reference fixing. She argues that reference to experiential properties should be introduced in the following, two-step way. First, we point to paradigm examples, such as suffering pain, feeling sad, or being visually presented with blueness. Second, we establish reference to a feature all the examples share, using metaphors and provisional descriptions (perhaps talking of ‘what it is like’ to have the properties), but without making any theoretical commitments as to the nature of the feature. This shared feature is what marks out experiential properties and thus phenomenal consciousness. Since illusionists deny the existence of experiential properties, Nida-Rümelin argues, they must either deny that this procedure picks out a common feature of experiential properties or say that experiential properties are never instantiated. Neither option, she argues, is attractive.
This argument is similar to Schwitzgebel’s, and my response is similar. I grant that the first step picks out real properties — the personal-level properties we call ‘being in pain’, ‘feeling sad’, ‘seeing a blue colour’, and so on. Illusionists do not deny that
something is going on when we are in pain or feeling sad. And I grant, too, that the second step establishes reference to a common feature of these properties. However, I deny that it is the sort of feature realists think it is. It is not some intrinsic quality, akin to the property characterized by the phenomenality language game. Rather, it is (roughly) the property of having a cluster of introspective representational states and dispositions that create the illusion that one is acquainted with some intrinsic quality. I am sure that this is not what Nida-Riimelin thinks the procedure picks out, but I don’t see how she can rule out the possibility. She makes it clear that in the second step reference is to be fixed by ostension, not description (she says that any descriptions used are merely an aid to identification and may not survive later theorizing — this issue, p. 168). So I am happy to concede the truth of realism about experiential properties
in this sense. However, this is a very weak kind of realism, which is compatible with the ontology of illusionism."
(pp. 287-8)
(Frankish, Keith. "Not Disillusioned: Reply to Commentators." In
Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness, edited by Keith Frankish, 256-289. Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2017. )
<QUOTE