Leontiskos wrote: ↑September 22nd, 2021, 7:37 pm
What reason do you have to think that Locke would impose the same moral constraints on natural goods as privately owned goods? Is there something in his writings that indicates this? It seems obvious to me that he wouldn’t impose the same constraints.
A couple of reasons. First, no moral distinction is made between the two in common law or common usage and understanding, and, second, because he goes to some length in the 2nd Essay to overcome that "lack of consent" objection. It is not up to Locke to decide what obligations ownership imposes; the concept itself imposes them (as we've agreed earlier).
There are many kinds of common ownerships --- partnerships, corporations, various types of clubs and co-ops, municipal property such as parks and streets, even marriages. All require the consent of the owners or their representatives before an individual, even a member of the group, may use the group's property for a private purpose.
GE Morton wrote: ↑September 21st, 2021, 11:32 pmYou argue below that the universal destination of goods doctrine "does not establish property rights." I'm certainly no authority on Catholic theology or social theory, but what I've been able to learn on that subject in the last couple hours strongly suggests that it does:
“God destined the earth and all it contains for all men and all peoples so that all created things would be shared fairly by all mankind under the guidance of justice tempered by charity" (Gaudium et Spes, 69). This principle is based on the fact that 'the original source of all that is good is the very act of God, who created both the earth and man, and who gave the earth to man so that he might have dominion over it by his work and enjoy its fruits' (Gen 1:28-29)" . . .
http://www.catholicceo.net/universal-destination-of-goods
Creating something establishes a property right, and giving the thing created conveys that right to the donee.
You are assuming “first possession,” which is the very thing in question. The text itself says nothing about a property right.
I don't understand. If God is the creator of the Earth, he is it's first possessor and therefore has a property right to it, does he not? And having that right he may convey that property to someone else, who will then have the right to it. No?
The text states the necessary and sufficient conditions for establishing a property right. It doesn't have to explicitly mention "property right."
GE Morton wrote: ↑September 21st, 2021, 11:32 pm“This right (emphasis added) applies to both 'the necessities of life and the tools for…progress'. (Pope St. Paul VI, 22)"
https://capp-usa.org/universal-destination-of-goods/
This is an odd one because the website is misquoting the source (link to source). The quote given is simply not found in the source at all. In contrast, the source at #22 says, “All other rights, whatever they may be, including the rights of property and free trade, are to be subordinated to this principle.” (emphasis added)
#22 does say, "Now if the earth truly was created to provide man with the necessities of life and the tools for his own progress, it follows that every man has the
right to glean what he needs from the earth" (emphasis added).
That is certainly a property right, and the "other rights" you quote above are those
other than this stated right.
Moving back to Locke from Catholicism, your assumption that Locke understood there to be a universal right that imposes the same constraints as the private right established by mixture of labor is quite strange. Locke clearly did not believe that. His whole purpose was to distinguish private property from the universal donation:
John Locke wrote:“Whether we consider natural reason, which tells us, that men, being once born, have a right to their preservation, and consequently to meat and drink, and such other things as nature affords for their subsistence: or revelation, which gives us an account of those grants God made of the world to Adam, and to Noah, and his sons, it is very clear, that God, as king David says, Psal. cxv. 16. has given the earth to the children of men; given it to mankind in common. But this being supposed, it seems to some a very great difficulty, how any one should ever come to have a property in any thing: I will not content myself to answer, that if it be difficult to make out property, upon a supposition that God gave the world to Adam, and his posterity in common, it is impossible that any man, but one universal monarch, should have any property upon a supposition, that God gave the world to Adam, and his heirs in succession, exclusive of all the rest of his posterity. But I shall endeavour to shew, how men might come to have a property in several parts of that which God gave to mankind in common, and that without any express compact of all the commoners.” (Second Treatise on Government, Chapter V, Section 25, emphasis mine)
Yes, that was indeed his purpose. My argument is that he failed to accomplish it. Laboring upon someone else's property, whether under a common or individual ownership, without the consent of the owner(s) does not confer any rights upon that laborer, either to the portion of the property labored upon or to the products of that labor, in any other situation. E.g., if I knowingly plant an apple tree on your property without your permission it, and all the apples it produces, instantly become your property. I have forfeited the labor exerted to plant it.
Here is Blackstone's take on Locke's labor theory:
"Mr. Locke says 'that the labour of a man’s body and the work of his hands we may say are properly his. Whatsoever then he removes out of the state that nature hath provided and left it in, he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his property.' On Govt. c. 5.
"But this argument seems to be a
petitio principii; for mixing labour with a thing can signify only to make an alteration in its shape or form; and if I had a right to the substance before any labour was bestowed upon it, that right still adheres to all that remains of the substance, whatever changes it may have undergone. If I had no right before, it is clear that I have none after; and we have not advanced a single step by this demonstration."
Blackstone, Commentaries, Vol. 1 - Books I & II. Chapter 1
https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/blacks ... perty-1753
GE Morton wrote: ↑September 21st, 2021, 11:32 pmThe farmer has a right to his crop, being its first possessor. He only has a right to the land if he is the first possessor of that as well. If he is not, then he requires the permission of the actual first possessor, or his successor in title, in order the use the land. The same would be true for any other good the farmer required to plant and nurture and harvest his crop --- seed, fertilizer, irrigation equipment, plows, etc. He must either buy them or rent them from their first possessors.
Okay, but I asked whether you think he has more right to his crop or his land, which you did not answer. The point is to call into question your binary legal approach, lest we fall into legal positivism. I omitted some parts of your reply that assume that the binary, legal approach is sufficient or irreducible. That is one of the main questions.
I thought I did answer that. He has
no right to the land, by hypothesis (he is, by hypothesis, leasing it from someone else). He has only a right to
use the land for the period and purposes set forth in the lease. He has a right to his crops, however, provided they were produced in accordance with the terms of the lease.
But again, I am not arguing for Locke’s position in isolation. I am claiming that his concept adds a useful nuance to first possession. This particular criticism of Locke that you keep reverting to is beside the point.
Well, I won't try to analyze or evaluate nuances. I don't think Locke was trying to add a nuance to the first possession criterion; he was trying to find a way around the original common ownership dogma so that the first possession criterion could apply.
GE Morton wrote: ↑September 21st, 2021, 11:32 pmWell, on its own that has a Platonic, essentialist, ring. Things don't have purposes in themselves; the only purpose anything has is the purpose to which some sentient creature applies it.
For Aristotle a purpose or end does not presuppose sentience. He would say everything has a final cause or an intrinsic teleology, and we can learn what this is by investigation. For example, the end of an acorn is an oak tree. That is what it aims at or is oriented towards. If we want we can aid it, for we know what conditions are favorable to it. We can water it and provide it with sunlight or rich soil, etc. When we walk through a forest we can identify good and bad oak trees. The same goes for fish and dogs and cats and centipedes. It is also true for humans, even if we are a great deal more complicated.
You seem to be equating
ends and
purposes. I agree (some) ends don't require sentience (such as your acorn/oak example), but purposes do; they imply an intention. Many natural processes have ends --- or milestones or waypoints we may treat as ends for some reason or our own --- but the termination point of a natural process is not a purpose. To return to the grain example, the Aristotelian "end,"
telos, or final cause of a kernel of wheat is to seed a new wheat plant; it is not to feed anyone. That it can be used for the latter is a purpose we sentient creatures give it.
Now I agree that "purpose" is often used as a synonym for "end." I find those uses to be somewhat loose and metaphorical. That use makes sense, however, IF one assumes that natural processes are elements of a system or design created by a Supreme Being. Then we have someone to whom we can properly attribute intents and purposes.
The other salient point concerning the
telos of a natural process or entity is that (absent the Supreme Being) it has no moral import; it is morally irrelevant. It only becomes morally relevant if the end of that process is given a purpose and value by some moral agent.
The upshot here is that you can't construe the UDG principle as embodying the Aristotelian
telos of a silo of grain. As I said, the
telos of wheat kernals is the seeding of new wheat plants. Feeding humans is a purpose
we give it.
No, teleological propositions are not supernatural propositions.
I agree, provided the propositions are not statements of divine purposes in disguise. But when that is the case they have no moral import.
GE Morton wrote: ↑September 21st, 2021, 11:32 pm
There is a constraint on the first possession principle which limits takings to the amount that the taker can put to productive use, i.e., a "no waste" constraint. I may not pick all the apples from a tree if 90% of them will rot. But if I have a way to preserve them --- e.g., by making cider or applesauce which will feed me for a year, then I may. Or if I make applesauce for sale to the public.
But why? How does that follow from first possession? Apparently it doesn’t, and that’s the point. First possession is incomplete and therefore must be supplemented by other principles, such as the universal destination of goods.
Again, I agree. That constraint is universally recognized in common law, and though it doesn't follow from the first possession principle, it follows from the theory I've been presenting. The moral significance of property is that it contributes to the welfare of its holder. So a rights claimnant may not claim more than he can derive benefit from, and has a duty, the Duty to Aid --- "another principle" --- to transfer any excess he may acquire to others who will benefit from it.
If you are going to nitpick Locke, then the same scrutiny should be applied to your own theories. That many people use something does not mean that ownership is common (that is a Lockean notion which relates to use or labor).
Of course it does. If no first possessor can be identified or title chain traced, then the property belongs to the current possessors ("possession is nine tenths of the law"). And, no, the notion of common property far predates Locke's theories.
"Although the principle is an oversimplification, it can be restated as: 'In a property dispute (whether real or personal), in the absence of clear and compelling testimony or documentation to the contrary, the person in actual, custodial possession of the property is presumed to be the rightful owner. The rightful owner shall have their possession returned to them; if taken or used. The shirt or blouse you are currently wearing is presumed to be yours, unless someone can prove that it is not.'"
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Possessio ... of_the_law