Steve3007 wrote: ↑September 6th, 2021, 7:44 amWell, you've complicated the issue with your "People have a right to keep their two legs . . ." That is a derivative right, a moral conclusion drawn from a natural right premise via a moral theory. The underlying premise is, "Alfie has a right to his two legs." That proposition, unlike your "Right to keep" premise, is strictly empirical --- it is true IFF Alfie was the first possessor of his two legs. If we then introduce a moral premise or theory which says, "People ought not take things from other people which they have acquired righteously," we can derive your "Right to keep" statement.
OK, so we agree that rights exist. We agree that they don't exist in the same sense that, for example, material objects exist (i.e. continuing to exist in the absence of minds) but they do exist in the same sense that other abstract concepts exist - as ideas in human minds. But (in my view) they are not in the same class as, for example, the abstract concept of natural laws. Natural laws, in my usage at least, means descriptions of patterns in what has been observed of the material world, the law of gravitation being an example. Although that description is an abstract concept which does not exist in the absence of minds and their observations, it purports to describe a relationship between matter which (it proposes) would exist in the absence of those minds. That is not the case with natural rights.
For example, we might describe "people are usually born with two legs" as a statement of natural law and "people have the right to keep the two legs with which they were born" as a statement of natural rights. As laws/principles they're both abstract concepts. But (in my view) the former purports to describe a fact about the extramental world whereas the latter purports to describe an opinion as to what people ought to do.
Propositions in the form "P has a right to x," where x is some particular tangible or intangible thing (property rights) or to take some action (liberty rights) are true-or-false statements with publicly verifiable truth conditions. And, yes, the relationship asserted would exist in the absence of minds, just as would "P lives in Chicago." But such propositions do indeed also have moral import, and can serve as premises in moral arguments.
The relationship between the person and the thing (e.g. "I have two legs") is not the right. The statement "I have the right to my legs" has a truth condition that is publicly verifiable only because it is the logical conclusion from the two statements "I was born with two legs" (empirical proposition) and "I have a right to the things with which I was born" (expression of what I think ought to be done if somebody tried to take my legs away).Your second statement, "I have a right to the things with which I was born" is derived from, "I was the first possessor of my two legs," and the definition of a "right."
Ooops, non sequitur. "Inextricably connected," yes. "IS a moral question," no. The truth conditions for "P has a right to x" neither include nor require any moral assumptions or inquiries. But the proposition does have moral import, and is typically asserted to evoke moral reflection. Such propositions are not meaningless without a moral context, but would seldom be asserted without one. Crusoe alone on his island still has a right to the coconut he found, but would have no occasion to assert it.Whether P has a right to x is not even a moral question. It is a strictly empirical, factual one. The relevant moral question is whether we ought, if P's claim is true, to respect that right.In my view the ought is inextricably connected to the right because if it isn't then the right is meaningless. Therefore the question of whether P has a natural or common right to x is a moral question.
Steve3007 wrote:The statement "People have a natural right to the things which they bring with them into the world because they acquired them without inflicting loss or injury on other moral agents" contains an opinion.Of course it contains an opinion. It is also my opinion that 2+2 = 4, and that Paris is the capital of France. Opinions are not contraries of "facts." That the (classical) meaning of "having a right" is as given above is an historical fact, as is whether P is the first possessor of x.
I disagree. In my usage, "2 + 2 = 4" and "Paris is the capital of France" are not opinions. They are statements of linguistic or logical conventions.They're both. The two characterizations are not mutually exclusive. An opinion is merely a belief that proposition P is the case. "It is Alfie's opinion that P" is equivalent to, "Alfie believes that P." P may be true or false, and if true, we say that P is a "fact." Whether P is true is decided by verifying its truth conditions; deciding whether Alfie believes that P involves an entirely different set of truth conditions.
"1. COUNTABLE NOUN [oft poss NOUN, NOUN that]
Your opinion about something is what you think or believe about it.
"3. UNCOUNTABLE NOUN
You can refer to the beliefs or views that people have as opinion."
https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dicti ... sh/opinion
The statement "People have a natural right to the things which they bring with them into the world..." is a statement as to what one believes ought to be done by various humans in various circumstances, as a result of some empirical facts.No. That statement is merely the definition of "natural right." It does, of course, have moral import, as do most assertions or claims of rights.
I don't think 2 + 2 ought to be 4. I don't think Paris ought to be the capital of France. I don't think I ought to have two legs. I don't think I ought to have brought them with me into the world. Those are not oughts. They are statements of what is the case either conventionally or empirically. As soon as I attach rights I introduce the ought, because, if my statement about rights is to have any meaning above and beyond the bare physical facts about my legs, it must be about what various people ought to do if various other people try to deprive me of my legs.You're equating what a proposition asserts with some "ought" which may follow from it, given some moral theory. Rights statements don't assert "oughts;" they assert empirical facts. No "oughts" are implied by them without an intervening moral premise or theory. "Steve has a right to his legs" is an empircal statement. "Depriving Steve of his legs would injure him" is an empirical statement. "One ought not deprive Steve of his legs" is a moral statment, which can be derived if a moral premise is added to those empirical statements, i.e., "one ought not inflict injuries on other moral agents."
I argued elsewhere that moral "oughts" are merely instrumental "oughts" --- assertions about what one ought to do if one seeks a certain goal. E.g., "If you want to drive a nail you ought to get a hammer." The "ought" there simply proposes that doing X will enable you to reach some goal Y, or at least get you closer to it. Such "ought" statements are also factual; either doing X will get you closer to Y or it won't. If the goal of morality, or a moral theory, is to devise rules which allow all agents in a social setting to maximize their welfare, then a rule to the effect that "one ought not inflict injuries on other moral agents" is an instrumental "ought," and either will or will not get us closer to that goal.
Thanks for post, Steve. Refreshing to see one that actually addresses the arguments, rather than spouting epithets and ad hominems.