Peter Holmes wrote: ↑February 7th, 2021, 1:57 pmIt has not always been kept clear in the history of philosophy. But the concepts involved are easily distinguishable.
1 The distinction between axiology and moral theory isn't clear cut.
A moral assertion expresses a moral value-judgement - which is an evaluation."Moral value judgment" embodies a confusion of concepts, as does the ubiquitous phrase, "moral values." A rational moral judgment (that an act is right or wrong) is not a value assessment of that act.
Value assignments are intrinsically subjective. Propositions asserting/assigning values are only cognitive if a valuer is specified. I.e., "X has value V" is non-cognitive (it has no determinable truth conditions). "X has value V to P" can be cognitive (we can observe P to see if he will give up V to secure X). Thus values are necessarily relative to valuers, and hence subjective.
Someone who pronounces an act right or wrong because he finds it unpleasant, distasteful, offensive, or inimical to some desire or preference he has is not doing ethics; he is merely expressing some values he holds --- all of which are subjective.
And anyway, arguments for the objectivity of assertions of non-moral value are as unsound as those for the assertion of moral rightness or wrongness. There's no objectivity here.All value assertions are indeed subjective, but not "unsound." Soundness applies to arguments, not propositions, which are either true or false. Value assertions may even be true, as long as a valuer is specified or implied.
That the goal of morality is to enable all agents to maximise their welfare is an opinion - not a fact.I acknowledged earlier that some philosophers have held that moral rules have a different goal, such as "living the good life," or conforming to "God's Will." But the central concern, the predominant thrust, of nearly all moral codes throughout history has been condemning acts which inflict loss or injury on other moral agents --- "Don't kill or maim," don't steal," "don't cheat," don't rape," etc., and encouraging acts which aid others "be kind," be generous," "keep your promises," etc. --- all rules necessary to make social life rewarding, and even possible.
That is, of course, a subjective goal --- all actions aim at some goal, and all goals are subjective. Someone who does not share that goal will have no use for these moral rules, just as a person not concerned with safe and efficient travel on highways will have no use for traffic rules. Those rules remain objective, however --- they either do or do not further that goal.
Your analysis of the function of a moral assertion, such as 'slavery is morally wrong' is incorrect. That assertion doesn't mean 'X is inconsistent with goal Y'. It means 'X is morally wrong, whatever the goal'. That we apply our moral assertions universally is one reason why we can mistakenly think of them as objective.Unless "Slavery is morally wrong" means inconsistent with some moral principle, and that principle embodies some goal, then the proposition is non-cognitive. It merely expresses a personal preference or value.