Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
By GE Morton
#352393
Peter Holmes wrote: March 9th, 2020, 6:21 am Just to tidy up and clarify my previous post.

It has been argued that claims about moral rightness and wrongness are about consistency with goals derived from axioms requiring no justification.

Axiom: Homosexuals are vermin.
Goal: Rid ourselves of vermin.
Advisory assertion: If we want to rid ourselves of vermin, then we [should/ought to/need to/must] rid ourselves of homosexuals.

This assertion is objective, because it has public truth conditions. And because it's about morality, then supposedly it's a 'moral assertion'.
Sarcasm notwithstanding, you're getting closer to understanding the argument here. But your straw-man argument above makes several mistakes.

"Homosexuals are vermin" cannot be an axiom in a moral theory, for 2 reasons. First, the axiom must express the aim or goal of the theory. Your "axiom" does not; it is merely a disparaging epithet. Secondly, axioms must be self-evident: widely, if not universally, understood and accepted as true (as you said, "requiring no justification"). Your "axiom" doesn't even have a truth value.

To clarify: "Moral" rules and principles are rules and principles governing interactions between agents in a social setting, having the aim of maximizing welfare for all agents (by reducing injuries and losses resulting from destructive interactions between agents, and fostering interactions which increase welfare for one or more agents).

The aim of a moral theory is to identify and develop those principles and rules in a systematic way (i.e., via methods that are rationally defensible).
Our thinking the axiom is morally wrong and repulsive (as I do) has no bearing on the nominal objectivity of the advisory assertion.
You're right, and that can be generalized: Agreement or disagreement with a goal has no bearing on the objectivity of any advisories proffered in support of that goal.
Our choice of a moral axiom, how ever we justify it, is subjective - a matter of opinion. And that single fact demolishes the argument for moral objectivity, ab initio.
Well, if we are able to justify it it cannot be subjective (I cannot "justify" my preference for chocolate over vanilla ice cream). And you just contradicted yourself. If Y is a moral goal, then by your own admission, advisories which demonstrably advance that goal are both moral and objective. Hence we have "moral objectivity."

You're confusing failing to share a goal with a lack of objectivity of proposed means to that goal.

You could re-state your argument above thus:

1. AXIOM: To develop rules and principles governing interactions between agents in a social setting, with the aim of ridding the world of homosexuals.
2. We ought yo kill any homosexual we encounter.
3. Etc.

But of course, the aim stated is hardly universally or widely shared, is not self-evident. Indeed, I'd argue that any rules or principles governing interactions between agents that did not have the aim I gave above would not be "moral" rules; that that aim is part of the definition of "moral." But the rules that ensue from your theory will (or can be) objective.
By GE Morton
#352394
Terrapin Station wrote: March 9th, 2020, 4:36 am
GE Morton wrote: March 8th, 2020, 8:39 pm Well, the proposition in question --- "Paris is the capital of France" --- says nothing about Paris's location
?? It certainly says something about Paris' location re how I interpret it.
Egads, will you cease with the "interpretation" irrelevancies? The proposition asserts a specific fact; it has specific truth conditions. No "interpreting" is necessary, unless you count knowing the meanings of the words involved "interpreting."
France, among other things, picks out a location. Given what capitals are, they're always located in what they're a capital of (they wouldn't necessarily be, but this is contingently the case). So the sentence tells me that rather than being in Laos, say, or Greenland, say, which are different locations, Paris is in France.
Yes, one may draw that inference, inductively, from the proposition. But it is irrelevant to the truth or falsity of the proposition.
By GE Morton
#352395
Belindi wrote: March 9th, 2020, 6:58 am Regarding GEMorton's example "Paris is the capital of France" whether or not the speaker intends the claim as a sort of geographical location in time and space, or whatever other motive she has for voicing the claim, her language behaviour is social.Or socio-cultural.
Of course it is. That is a given, a universal. But that fact does not render propositions subjective.
Kuhn has shown science is a social activity. Pure objectivity is impossible and must remain an ideal to aspire to but never to be realised in this world.
I have no idea what "pure objectivity" might consist of, or require. That is a idealistic concept that seems to presume some sort of transcendental realm of existence or an omniscient observer or a sub specie aeternitatis perspective --- none of which concepts have any explanatory utility. They are vacuous notions.

It is propositions, not persons, which are objective or subjective; a proposition is objective if its truth conditions are public. A person can be said to be objective or subjective to the extent the propositions he utters are objective or subjective.
The best we can do in the direction of objectivity is relative true knowledge and relatively true judgements.Those are founded on the true nature of events as if there be such as state as over arching order in the universe.This over arching order is what I call Nature. Some call it God, I call it Nature.
Any proposition you utter presuming to describe the "true knowledge" and the "true nature of events" will be either objective or subjective, depending upon whether its truth conditions are public or private.
Since we are inescapably subjective we suffer from a feeling of existential angst having no authority but our own.
Speak for yourself!
Any man who lacks an element of neuroticism in his psyche cannot live for long.It is neuroticism that makes GEMorton and any authentic person here able to think responsibly.
Egads, Belindi!
By creation
#352396
Terrapin Station wrote: March 9th, 2020, 9:41 am
creation wrote: March 9th, 2020, 8:30 am The answer to the question is: Agreement and acceptance by all.
In what way does that make anything objective?
In order for me to answer this question so that you could understand my answer I will need to know how you define the word 'objective' here?
Terrapin Station wrote: March 9th, 2020, 9:41 am What work does "objectivity" do if what we mean by "objective" is "everyone agrees"?
What work does "subjectivity" do if what we mean by "subjective" is "individually one agrees"?
By Peter Holmes
#352407
GE Morton wrote: March 9th, 2020, 9:41 pm
Peter Holmes wrote: March 9th, 2020, 6:21 am Just to tidy up and clarify my previous post.

It has been argued that claims about moral rightness and wrongness are about consistency with goals derived from axioms requiring no justification.

Axiom: Homosexuals are vermin.
Goal: Rid ourselves of vermin.
Advisory assertion: If we want to rid ourselves of vermin, then we [should/ought to/need to/must] rid ourselves of homosexuals.

This assertion is objective, because it has public truth conditions. And because it's about morality, then supposedly it's a 'moral assertion'.
Sarcasm notwithstanding, you're getting closer to understanding the argument here. But your straw-man argument above makes several mistakes.

"Homosexuals are vermin" cannot be an axiom in a moral theory, for 2 reasons. First, the axiom must express the aim or goal of the theory. Your "axiom" does not; it is merely a disparaging epithet. Secondly, axioms must be self-evident: widely, if not universally, understood and accepted as true (as you said, "requiring no justification"). Your "axiom" doesn't even have a truth value.

To clarify: "Moral" rules and principles are rules and principles governing interactions between agents in a social setting, having the aim of maximizing welfare for all agents (by reducing injuries and losses resulting from destructive interactions between agents, and fostering interactions which increase welfare for one or more agents).

The aim of a moral theory is to identify and develop those principles and rules in a systematic way (i.e., via methods that are rationally defensible).
Our thinking the axiom is morally wrong and repulsive (as I do) has no bearing on the nominal objectivity of the advisory assertion.
You're right, and that can be generalized: Agreement or disagreement with a goal has no bearing on the objectivity of any advisories proffered in support of that goal.
Our choice of a moral axiom, how ever we justify it, is subjective - a matter of opinion. And that single fact demolishes the argument for moral objectivity, ab initio.
Well, if we are able to justify it it cannot be subjective (I cannot "justify" my preference for chocolate over vanilla ice cream). And you just contradicted yourself. If Y is a moral goal, then by your own admission, advisories which demonstrably advance that goal are both moral and objective. Hence we have "moral objectivity."

You're confusing failing to share a goal with a lack of objectivity of proposed means to that goal.

You could re-state your argument above thus:

1. AXIOM: To develop rules and principles governing interactions between agents in a social setting, with the aim of ridding the world of homosexuals.
2. We ought yo kill any homosexual we encounter.
3. Etc.

But of course, the aim stated is hardly universally or widely shared, is not self-evident. Indeed, I'd argue that any rules or principles governing interactions between agents that did not have the aim I gave above would not be "moral" rules; that that aim is part of the definition of "moral." But the rules that ensue from your theory will (or can be) objective.
I conclude it's pointless to refute your argument, because you just ignore or evade the refutation. Thanks for the craic.
User avatar
By Sy Borg
#352412
Terrapin Station wrote: March 9th, 2020, 9:41 am
creation wrote: March 9th, 2020, 8:30 am The answer to the question is: Agreement and acceptance by all.
In what way does that make anything objective? What work does "objectivity" do if what we mean by "objective" is "everyone agrees"?
It disappears into a cloud of whimsy because the chances of everyone agreeing on any issue are zero.

I'm not much keen about morality only being about humans either. Welfare of other species should be part of any moral equation too, but too often is treated as trivia. This is at least partly why humanity is in such a godawful mess today, due to the unacknowledged "services" provided by ecosystems, and our mistreatment of food animals is also coming back to haunt us again ... SARS, avian flu, Covid-19.
#352418
GE Morton wrote: March 9th, 2020, 9:53 pm Egads, will you cease with the "interpretation" irrelevancies?
Interpretation is how language necessarily works.
The proposition asserts a specific fact;
The proposition is the meaning of the sentence. Meaning is per individual, it exists in individual's heads as something their brains are doing. And specifically it's the associative act an individual makes re, for example, associating "text marks" (a la pixels on a screen for example) with concepts they have in mind, or with memories, or with something they're looking at, etc.

Propositions assert things to individuals, and what they assert is determined by how an individual thinks about the proposition. Hence why interpretation is a necessary part of the equation.
it has specific truth conditions.
The truth conditions are (a) whatever the individual takes the proposition to be asserting, per the individual's subjective application of meaning, (b) whatever the individual takes to be the requirements for the proposition to match something else, and (c) the individual's judgment as to whether the proposition matches re (a) and (b)--the "matching" relation in question is also something that our brains do, and that can differ (aside from nominalistic differing, which is necessarily the case) per individual.
No "interpreting" is necessary, unless you count knowing the meanings of the words involved "interpreting."
We assign meanings. The text marks don't have meanings "on their own." Because of what meaning is, it can only occur in an individual's mind. There's no way to make the associative act obtain externally. It's not the sort of thing that falls under the property purviews of any other "substance" aside from brains.
Yes, one may draw that inference, inductively, from the proposition. But it is irrelevant to the truth or falsity of the proposition.
Not at all on my interpretation, because if it were to say "Paris is the capital of Laos," that would be false on my view because "we've got the wrong place."
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By creation
#352422
Greta wrote: March 10th, 2020, 6:56 am
Terrapin Station wrote: March 9th, 2020, 9:41 am

In what way does that make anything objective? What work does "objectivity" do if what we mean by "objective" is "everyone agrees"?
It disappears into a cloud of whimsy because the chances of everyone agreeing on any issue are zero.
LOL

Do human beings need air to live?

If anyone disagrees they do, then put them in a room, tell them we are going to remove the air, and show us how human beings do not need air to live. Then, ask them, Do you want to continue?

It is very possible to quickly learn and see the issues that everyone agrees on and with.

By the way, this is HOW objective morality is discovered, learned, and understood.
Greta wrote: March 10th, 2020, 6:56 am I'm not much keen about morality only being about humans either.
Who has even suggested morality is only being about humans?

If human being thought that morality was only about them, then this just shows the stupidity that human beings can have and are capable of.
Greta wrote: March 10th, 2020, 6:56 am Welfare of other species should be part of any moral equation too, but too often is treated as trivia.
Why is this being brought up after quoting what I have said.

Absolutely EVERY species is EQUAL in morality issues, well to me anyway.
Greta wrote: March 10th, 2020, 6:56 am This is at least partly why humanity is in such a godawful mess today, due to the unacknowledged "services" provided by ecosystems, and our mistreatment of food animals is also coming back to haunt us again ... SARS, avian flu, Covid-19.
You have, so far, really missed or misconstrued what I was saying and getting at.
#352425
creation wrote: March 10th, 2020, 7:55 am By the way, this is HOW objective morality is discovered, learned, and understood.
So you're claiming that there actually are moral stances that everyone agrees on?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By GE Morton
#352432
Greta wrote: March 10th, 2020, 6:56 am
I'm not much keen about morality only being about humans either. Welfare of other species should be part of any moral equation too, but too often is treated as trivia.
Most contemporary moral philosophers do consider the welfare of (some) other species to be within the purview of moral philosophy, though they are usually deemed "moral subjects," or "moral patients," instead of "moral agents," and the duties of moral agents to them differs from those due other moral agents. They don't treat the issue as trivia.
User avatar
By Sculptor1
#352440
Greta wrote: March 10th, 2020, 6:56 am
I'm not much keen about morality only being about humans either. Welfare of other species should be part of any moral equation too, but too often is treated as trivia.
Anyone who loves their dog knows what you mean.
It takes very little cruelty directed at dogs to get my outrage running.

https://uk.yahoo.com/news/therapy-dog-d ... 10596.html

Most mammals have the same emotional tendencies that cause humans to think about moral behaviour.
Were we lacking in those emotions I doubt we would have any interests in the welfare of others of any kind. In fact I doubt we would have any particular will to live or have purpose.

The purity of the subjectiveness is wrought large when you consider the wide ranging spectrum of which humans or animals are see to deserve moral consideration and to what degree. This varies so much historically, culturally and personally, that any case for objectivity is laughable.
#352447
GE Morton wrote: March 10th, 2020, 12:07 pm Most contemporary moral philosophers do consider the welfare of (some) other species to be within the purview of moral philosophy
That seems like a very dubious claim. Do you have survey data to back it up?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#352448
GE Morton wrote: March 10th, 2020, 12:07 pm Most contemporary moral philosophers do consider the welfare of (some) other species to be within the purview of moral philosophy
Ah--sorry, I misread you as saying DON'T, not "do"
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By Sy Borg
#352450
Sculptor1 wrote: March 10th, 2020, 3:49 pm
Greta wrote: March 10th, 2020, 6:56 am
I'm not much keen about morality only being about humans either. Welfare of other species should be part of any moral equation too, but too often is treated as trivia.
Anyone who loves their dog knows what you mean.
It takes very little cruelty directed at dogs to get my outrage running.

https://uk.yahoo.com/news/therapy-dog-d ... 10596.html

Most mammals have the same emotional tendencies that cause humans to think about moral behaviour.
Were we lacking in those emotions I doubt we would have any interests in the welfare of others of any kind. In fact I doubt we would have any particular will to live or have purpose.

The purity of the subjectiveness is wrought large when you consider the wide ranging spectrum of which humans or animals are see to deserve moral consideration and to what degree. This varies so much historically, culturally and personally, that any case for objectivity is laughable.
Yes. Humans are self-obsessed. That is how so many humans can posit that a tiny piece of protoplasmic muck (aka a human embryo) is more important than any sentient, intelligent and bonded adult mammal of another species. Thus, those who speak of a "right to life" will typically speak of the sanctity of life while chomping down eat large portions of factory-farmed steak and/or pork every day.

Humans tend to see any moral system that is fair to humans as fair per se. Other sentient beings do not count, being largely treated as a moral null unless they are considered to be loveable, valuable or useful to humans.

Of course, many other social animals are similarly solipsist and ruthlessly bloody-minded, but none of those species claim to be far morally superior to all others.

I have watched toilet paper panic buying in a recent days in response to the smallest hint of a supply shock, with people walking out of shops with months of toilet rolls, ensuring that others will have none. It reminds me that human moral superiority is an illusion and delusion. We are exactly as selfish and immoral as wolves, bears and lions. Only a thin veneer of civilisation providing a sense of security stands between humans and total moral breakdown.
  • 1
  • 50
  • 51
  • 52
  • 53
  • 54
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


If you haven't already, you can sign up to be per[…]

A naturalist's epistemology??

Gertie wrote From your posts I get the impressio[…]

One reason our vision might be processed at the ba[…]

What is the ancestry delusion in wild cultures? […]