Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
By GE Morton
#352050
Terrapin Station wrote: March 6th, 2020, 6:16 pm
Which is the whole gist of pointing out that when x is distressing to S and not-x is distressing to R, we have a problem for "maximizing well-being."
No problem at all. Because "well-being" does not consist in, and is not measured by, feelings, moods, emotions, or anything else "in people's heads." It is measured by the extent to which someone is able to secure the things he values, as evidenced by his observable behavior --- the things he invests his time, energy, other resources to secure.

I agree there is a broader sense of "well-being" which takes those affective states into account. Most people would be unwilling to claim that a person suffering from depression is in a high state of well-being. But those responses and states are idiosyncratic, unpredictable, beyond the control of other agents, and no moral principle or rule addressing them could be universalized. Moral philosophy can only be concerned with "material well-being," because those are the only aspects of well-being that can be objectively identified and measured.

Moral principles and rules are concerned with human actions ---- not with what people think or feel, but with what they do.
By GE Morton
#352053
Kaz_1983 wrote: March 6th, 2020, 7:35 am It depends on how you define morality.
Indeed it does. Any one setting out to develop a moral theory, or propose moral principles, must first decide what "morality" is, what that theory, those principles and rules, aim to accomplish.
By GE Morton
#352054
Peter Holmes wrote: March 6th, 2020, 9:13 am
Your criterion for what you incorrectly call the objectivity of a moral theory is the consistency of its moral assertions. But that means any moral theory can be objective. So your claim that 'vernacular' moral theories are subjective - unlike your supposedly 'sound' theory - is flatly false, by your own definition - and merely an expression of your prejudice passed off as a fact. Moral objectivism in a nutshell, come to think about it.
Yes, a vernacular moral theory could be objective. But none of them existing are (that I know of). They are amalgams of religious dogmas, conditioned responses, cultural tropes, and personal emotional response patterns, jumbled together with no thought of consistency.
#352055
GE Morton wrote: March 6th, 2020, 7:52 pm It is measured by the extent to which someone is able to secure the things he values, as evidenced by his observable behavior
Valuing something isn't an observable behavior. It's a mental state. Observable behavior is taken as indirect evidence of the mental state.

Nevertheless, people usually value not being distressed, and you can see indirect evidence of this via observable behavior. This is often in conflict with other people, because S will be distressed by x while R is distressed by not-x.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By GE Morton
#352056
Terrapin Station wrote: March 6th, 2020, 8:10 pm
Valuing something isn't an observable behavior. It's a mental state.
Oh, but it is. The only thing that justifies my claim that "Alfie values X" is his observable efforts to secure X. That behavior is the direct evidence for the truth of that proposition. I may infer or hypothesize that he has some mental state that accompanies or provokes that behavior, but that hypothesis is not necessary to confirm that "Alfie values X."

That claim of yours leads to the same reductio ad absurdum to which your claim that meanings are mental events leads. If meanings and values are "things in people's heads," then verbal communication is impossible, and no value statements are cognitive, because no one can know what is in someone's head except the person whose head it is.
Observable behavior is taken as indirect evidence of the mental state.
Yes, it is. But it is DIRECT, and definitive, evidence that Alfie values X.
#352058
GE Morton wrote: March 6th, 2020, 8:30 pm
Terrapin Station wrote: March 6th, 2020, 8:10 pm
Valuing something isn't an observable behavior. It's a mental state.
Oh, but it is.
No, it's not. It's a mental state.
The only thing that justifies my claim that "Alfie values X" is his observable efforts to secure X.
How is he trying secure X behaviorally sans your interpretation of that, even?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Kaz_1983
#352062
GE Morton wrote: March 6th, 2020, 8:02 pm
Kaz_1983 wrote: March 6th, 2020, 7:35 am It depends on how you define morality.
Indeed it does. Any one setting out to develop a moral theory, or propose moral principles, must first decide what "morality" is, what that theory, those principles and rules, aim to accomplish.
See I believe that "morality" is independent of our wants and desires and in my opinion for "morality" to make sense it must be intrinsically action-guiding.

I don't believe morality is true-apt. Now I'm not rejecting "morality", I'm just holding the position of an agnostic on whether God exists or not.. replace God with "morality"
By GE Morton
#352063
Terrapin Station wrote: March 6th, 2020, 8:40 pm
How is he trying secure X behaviorally sans your interpretation of that, even?
Whether Alfie values X has nothing to do with any "interpreting" on my part. That is not among the truth conditions for "Alfie values X," which consist of behaviors on Alfie's part. I am not the subject of the proposition.
By Belindi
#352070
GE Morton wrote: March 6th, 2020, 12:29 pm
Belindi wrote: March 5th, 2020, 7:07 am Objective morality is the same as morality that is necessarily so. 'Objective' means 'necessary'.
Well, that would be an eclectic definition of "objective."

"Objective" and "subjective" are properties of propositions, like "true" and "false." A proposition is objective if its truth conditions are public; subjective if they are private.

Moral propositions, e.g., "One ought to do (or ought not do) X" are objective if their truth conditions are public, verifiable by any suitably situated observer. "Ought" statements, whether in moral propositions or elsewhere, are instrumental, they relate to some goal, acknowledged or implied. "You ought to do X" means, "X is an effective or necessary means of accomplishing Y," with Y being the goal. Whether a given X is or is not effective or necessary for accomplishing a given Y is usually objective.
You say "( "Ought" statements-----------relate to some goal----" . I agree. Goal and criterion whether stated or implied are similar as goal is a variety of criterion. For instance " If you want to be a doctor you will have to study very hard": "You need to practise handling a car before you can drive on the road". "Pass the ball to the left winger!" " Good! You understand linear perspective." " You sure can make good soup!" Are goal directed and all explicitly or implicitly imply criteria.

"I love you" "I am a human being" and "That's a pony not a horse" are not goal directed but refer to fixed states which are not in transition towards goals. A very subjective feeling of pain may be commented on as "Ouch!" or "On the scale of one to ten my pain was nine". In all cases of a subjective utterance the goal is implied by the social situation which may be a doctor's consulting room to children at play.The goal is to let the other know how one feels and this is either a) purposive or b) it's unconsidered reaction.The goal may be b)to refer to fellowship in experience of pain, or it may a) refer to an implicit cultural belief that the doctor at that time and place exists to help the patient.
If your untrained puppy nips you you should squeal or say a sharp "Ouch!" so the puppy learns biting hurts you . Dogs and very young children know this in the form of reactions(biologically) and we know this in the form of acquired knowledge(culturally).

No utterance is value neutral except when it's about the measurement itself e.g. "Haemoglobin carries oxygen" which has empirical and cultural criteria , and "1+1=2" which is universal but is deductive and tautological.

All inductively based propositions are goal or criteria laden . The goal may be immediate or mediated by a criterion. The only objective propositions are deductive as for mathematical or logical tautologies.

There are only two ways out of this dilemma. 1. God, or cosmic order. Pythagoras conflated logical tautologies and empirical facts such as musical harmonies.
2. Nature which unlike God implies no element of supernatural order of being but is otherwise like God as it's cause of itself.
#352077
GE Morton wrote: March 6th, 2020, 10:25 pm
Terrapin Station wrote: March 6th, 2020, 8:40 pm
How is he trying secure X behaviorally sans your interpretation of that, even?
Whether Alfie values X has nothing to do with any "interpreting" on my part. That is not among the truth conditions for "Alfie values X," which consist of behaviors on Alfie's part. I am not the subject of the proposition.
So that's how he's trying to secure x behaviorally sans your interpretation? Three claims about what's not the case?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Peter Holmes
#352121
GE Morton wrote: March 6th, 2020, 1:30 pm
Peter Holmes wrote: March 6th, 2020, 4:36 am
Whether we're talking about moral theories, principles, axioms, goals , codes or rules, the only things that can be objective or subjective are assertions. And assertions that express moral opinions - it is right to maximise the well-being of all agents - slavery is wrong - are subjective.

Adopting any moral theory, principle, axiom, goal, code or rule - sound or otherwise - is a choice, and is therefore subjective.
We've covered this, and I agree with respect to axioms and goals. Axioms are deemed true a priori. If a goal is set forth as the axiom of a theory, then it is accepted a priori. One may accept or reject the axioms of any theory. One may reject the axioms of Euclid's geometry. But then you'll face the task of finding other means of solving the thousands of daily problems that geometry allows us to solve.

The codes, rules, and principles that may be derived from a set of axioms, however, are objective --- they either do or do not advance the goal, either are or are not consistent with the axiom.

You can't seem to grasp that an "ought" statement can be objective whether or not the goal is objective. It can be, because the "ought" statement references the goal; it is a conditional --- "If you wish to do X, you must (or should) do Y." Propositions of that form can be true and objective.
Let's be precise: a goal Y is never objective, so that isn't the issue. And wanting goal Y is always subjective. The claim that action X leads to goal Y may be true and objective. But that doesn't establish the objectivity of a moral assertion, such as 'slavery is wrong', or 'it's right to maximise the well-being of all agents'.

"Objective" doesn't mean, "Agreed to by everyone," or, "true of 'external reality'," or, "From God's point of view," or anything with any metaphysical/ontological implications.
I agree that consensus and divine perspective have nothing to do with objectivity. But what does your definition of an objective assertion - 'with public truth conditions' - mean, if it isn't something to do with 'external reality'? (I may have misunderstood your point here.)

The real issue here is, "What is the aim, goal, of moral theories, moral codes, moral rules?" If you profess to interested in "morality" you have to answer that question somehow.
No, that's not the issue here at all. We're discussing what could make morality objective. That moral theories, codes and rules have one aim or goal is a matter of opinion - as is the claim that we should have such an aim or goal at all, let alone a particular aim or goal. And none of these confers objectivity on moral aims, goals, codes or rules.

I am interested in morality, which is why I'm concerned to demolish the delusion and expose the lie that morality - more precisely moral assertions - are or can be objective. That lie has encouraged and justified a great deal of human wickedness.
By Belindi
#352137
If nature is taken to be what is the case then people who know most about nature, including the human sciences, natural sciences, and humanities are more likely to live well.
By GE Morton
#352172
Peter Holmes wrote: March 7th, 2020, 11:53 am
GE Morton wrote: March 6th, 2020, 1:30 pm
You can't seem to grasp that an "ought" statement can be objective whether or not the goal is objective. It can be, because the "ought" statement references the goal; it is a conditional --- "If you wish to do X, you must (or should) do Y." Propositions of that form can be true and objective.
Let's be precise: a goal Y is never objective, so that isn't the issue. And wanting goal Y is always subjective. The claim that action X leads to goal Y may be true and objective. But that doesn't establish the objectivity of a moral assertion, such as 'slavery is wrong' . . ."
"Slavery is wrong," as a stand-alone proposition, may be subjective, because it means no more than, "I don't approve of slavery." If the utterer intends it to mean anything more than that, if he believes it has some "objective" truth value --- a truth value independent of his personal opinion --- then he will be assuming some criterion of "rightness" and "wrongness."

When people pronounce some act morally wrong they usually believe they are saying something more defensible, and more objective, than merely uttering a personal preference. They have some underlying moral principle --- some moral axiom --- in mind. If you ask someone who declares, "Slavery is wrong," WHY it is wrong, he'll try to give some answer:

"It is against God's will."

"It is illegal."

"It conflicts with the principle that all men are created equal."

"It causes suffering, and one should not make others suffer."

Etc. What he is not likely to answer is, "Because I don't like it."

People believe their moral judgments are grounded in some larger truth. When that is the case, then the proposition is actually a conditional, "If X is the case, or if you believe X, then slavery is wrong."

Just like "should" and "ought," moral rightness and wrongness are instrumental. To call any action "wrong" is to say it conflicts with, is inconsistent with, some standard, some rule accepted as valid or sound, or with the attainment of some adopted goal. Enslaving someone is wrong for the same reason that driving on the left side of the road (in the US) is wrong, or connecting the black wire to the neutral bus in an electrical panel is wrong --- they are all acts which conflict with some accepted standard, are inconsistent with some accepted principle, or will not advance one toward some chosen goal. Whether they are or are not compatible or consistent with that standard or goal is usually objective.

Upshot: if you declare some act to be morally wrong, and you mean something more substantive than that you don't like it, then you will have some broader goal or principle in mind, and you are declaring the act in question to be inconsistent with it. Whether the act in question is or is not consistent with that goal or principle is usually objective. Whether the larger principle is sound, or the goal worth pursuing, is a separate question. The reasons for adopting any principle or goal are always pragmatic, including the moral "Fundamental Principle" I gave earlier.
"Objective" doesn't mean, "Agreed to by everyone," or, "true of 'external reality'," or, "From God's point of view," or anything with any metaphysical/ontological implications.
I agree that consensus and divine perspective have nothing to do with objectivity. But what does your definition of an objective assertion - 'with public truth conditions' - mean, if it isn't something to do with 'external reality'? (I may have misunderstood your point here.)
It means that the state of affairs asserted in the proposition can be confirmed or disconfirmed by any suitably situated observer. "It is raining outside" is objective. That means that anyone in that area can confirm it by looking out the window or stepping outside. That criterion, BTW, makes no assumptions about any "external reality." The speaker and observers may all be solipsists, but they'll still be able to confirm or disconfirm that proposition. If they experience the percepts the proposition predicts, it is objective, even if they all consider it (and each other) parts of a hallucination.
The real issue here is, "What is the aim, goal, of moral theories, moral codes, moral rules?" If you profess to interested in "morality" you have to answer that question somehow.
No, that's not the issue here at all. We're discussing what could make morality objective. That moral theories, codes and rules have one aim or goal is a matter of opinion - as is the claim that we should have such an aim or goal at all, let alone a particular aim or goal. And none of these confers objectivity on moral aims, goals, codes or rules.
As I said above, if you make any sort of declaration that doing X is wrong, you will probably have some goal or broader principle in mind, and you will probably be claiming that X is incompatible with that goal or principle. Whether it is or not is (usually) objective. If you don't, then you will merely be declaring that you don't like X --- a fact that will interest no one, and certainly not persuade anyone to change their own opinion of X. If we want moral discussions, arguments, to be meaningful and persuasive we need to set forth, and justify, those proffered goals or principles.
I am interested in morality, which is why I'm concerned to demolish the delusion and expose the lie that morality - more precisely moral assertions - are or can be objective. That lie has encouraged and justified a great deal of human wickedness.
It is not the claim that a moral judgment or rule is objective that results in the wickedness. It is the fact that the underlying goal of that rule or judgment is wicked.
User avatar
By Sy Borg
#352174
So vague, GE. it's easy to keep people arguing for fifty pages about just about any topic if you stick to generalities. So we have fifty pages of not much.

How about you set out the exact objective morals to be critiqued by the forum? All you need to do is set out this "objective" moral theory in detail so others can provide decisive challenges to your ideas. At this stage you have shielded your ideas by sticking to generalities that can always be moulded and framed to give the impression of honest debate.

Where is this objective moral theory that applies to all cultures in all places (certainly not to all species)? In your imagination.
By GE Morton
#352177
Greta wrote: March 7th, 2020, 10:15 pm
How about you set out the exact objective morals to be critiqued by the forum?
Well, that would be the subject of another thread. The subject of this thread is, "What could make morality objective?" That entails a discussion of what objectivity is, what morality is, and what moral propositions assert. Which is what this thread, for the most part, has covered. Before those issues are settled there is no point in setting out a moral theory and claiming it is objective.
  • 1
  • 48
  • 49
  • 50
  • 51
  • 52
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


This topic is about the February 2025 Philosophy […]

You see nothing because you don't want to […]

I agree. But why should we consider liberta[…]

Quite true. We are not in a place at many occasion[…]