Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
#351538
GE Morton wrote: March 2nd, 2020, 11:24 pm Well, you're right that behavior is not the same thing as "mentality." But if you want propositions concerning preferences to be cognitive --- to have determinable truth values --- then you'll use the term to refer to observable behaviors.
You take the behavior as indirect evidence of the mental state. Why doesn't that work?

Are you saying that you don't accept any indirect evidence of anything as support for claims?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#351561
I think the following demonstrates the absurdity of moral objectivism.

P1: If we want goal Y, then we must do X.
P2: We want goal Y.
C: Therefore we must do X.

For the sake of this argument, the nature of goal Y is irrelevant. We can insert any goal we like, moral or otherwise.

P1 and P2 may be true, in which case the argument is not only valid, but also sound.

But wanting goal Y is a matter of preference, and is therefore subjective.

The claim that we must want goal Y is a matter of opinion, and is therefore subjective.

I think there's no way around this for moral objectivists. But I may be wrong. Can anyone see a way?
#351577
The big problem with it, again, is that it doesn't follow that you must or that it's better to try to achieve a goal than otherwise.

Sure, many people think that, and you can even use it to define "goal" if you want, but nevertheless, it's not an objective fact that we must or should do this, or that that's how we should define goal. And plenty of people have what they'd call goals that they don't feel it's better to try to achieve. The fact that someone might refuse to call that a goal doesn't amount to it being an objective fact that it's not a goal, etc.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By Peter Holmes
#351585
Terrapin Station wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 11:00 am The big problem with it, again, is that it doesn't follow that you must or that it's better to try to achieve a goal than otherwise.

Sure, many people think that, and you can even use it to define "goal" if you want, but nevertheless, it's not an objective fact that we must or should do this, or that that's how we should define goal. And plenty of people have what they'd call goals that they don't feel it's better to try to achieve. The fact that someone might refuse to call that a goal doesn't amount to it being an objective fact that it's not a goal, etc.
Agreed. You're right that P1 doesn't follow. My point is that, even if it did, so that the argument is valid and sound, that still doesn't establish moral objectivity. It's 'wanting' the goal, whatever it is, that undermines the case for objectivity. But point taken.
By Peter Holmes
#351587
Terrapin Station

As I'm sure you see, I'm trying to head off GEM's argument that modal 'must', 'should' or 'ought to' in the P1 consequent is merely instrumental, rather than moral.

Can you suggest a way of phrasing P1 to do that? Or would a note explaining the lack of entailment do - having said that this is how objectivists must or usually do formulate their argument?
By GE Morton
#351595
Peter Holmes wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 6:46 am
If you're using 'right or wrong' non-morally, as 'factually correct/incorrect' seems to indicate, then presumably you mean 'true or false'. So you are really saying: 'opinions are true or false - so moral opinions are true or false'.
Yes.
But only factual assertions have truth-value. And only assertions can be objective - with public truth conditions.
Yes.
To say 'this act is morally wrong' is true or false - that this assertion of an opinion has public truth conditions and is therefore objective - merely begs the question. You're not showing that it does, you're flatly asserting that it does.
I'm not sure what question you think is being begged.

Your assumption seems to be that opinions, judgments, beliefs are not factual assertions (propositions). But they are. Calling them opinions, judgments, beliefs merely means the speaker acknowledges that he lacks conclusive evidence for the proposition, or someone else believes he doesn't. But he is still asserting a proposition, which is either true or false. E.g.:

"It is my opinion (belief, judgment) that slavery is wrong."

The embedded proposition is, "Slavery is wrong." That proposition is true or false. It is true if slavery conflicts with the axiom and postulates of the theory; it is false if slavery does not conflict with those postulates. Whether it conflicts or does not is a factual or logical matter, and is objective.

With any other subject matter this "right/wrong" would be understood as the instrumental, or factual, sense of those terms. E.g.,

"It is my opinion that we turned the wrong way at that last intersection."

The embedded proposition is, "We turned the wrong way at that last intersection." That proposition is true or false. It is true if the left turn leads away from our destination; it is false it leads toward the destination.

If the proposition embedded in the expression, judgment, belief is true (or false) then the opinion, judgment, belief is true (or false).

Moral judgments made in the context of a sound, rational moral theory are not expressions of personal values, emotional states, conditioned responses, cultural norms, or anything of the kind. They are claims that a certain act or practice is consistent or inconsistent with the axioms and theorems of that theory. Those claims are either true or false and are objective; they have public truth conditions.
And that says it all. I think our discussion has run its course. For me, at least, it's been salutary. Thanks.
Giving up so quickly? But I also enjoyed the dialogue. It has been more challenging than most here.
By GE Morton
#351597
Peter Holmes wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 11:30 am Terrapin Station

As I'm sure you see, I'm trying to head off GEM's argument that modal 'must', 'should' or 'ought to' in the P1 consequent is merely instrumental, rather than moral.
It is not an "either/or" matter. An instrumental "ought" merely means that doing X is a necessary or useful for attaining some goal. A moral "ought" is an just an instrumental "ought" when the goal is a moral one.
By GE Morton
#351599
Terrapin Station wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 11:00 am The big problem with it, again, is that it doesn't follow that you must or that it's better to try to achieve a goal than otherwise.
Well, I make no claim that one must try to achieve any particular goal. But if someone decides he will be better off not pursuing some goal than pursuing it, then he has abandoned that goal. It is no longer a goal for him.
The fact that someone might refuse to call that a goal doesn't amount to it being an objective fact that it's not a goal, etc.
The only "objective fact" about the meaning of the word "goal" is how the word is used by English speakers. That is as follows:

"Definition of goal
1: the end toward which effort is directed : AIM"

https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/goal

An end to which no effort is directed is not a goal.
#351601
Following TS's just criticism of my attempt to show that moral objectivism is a mistake, here's another go.

P1: If we want goal Y, then we must do X.
P2: We want goal Y.
C: Therefore we must do X.

For the sake of this argument, the nature of goal Y is irrelevant. We can insert any goal we like, moral or otherwise.

If P1 and P2 are true, the argument is not only valid, but also sound. And negating every clause in the argument maintains its soundness.

But P1 is false, because wanting goal Y need not entail any action X.

And anyway, wanting goal Y is a matter of preference, and is therefore subjective.

The claim that we must want goal Y is a matter of opinion, and is therefore subjective.

I think there's no way around this for moral objectivists. But I may be wrong. Can anyone see a way?
#351602
GE Morton wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 1:02 pm
Peter Holmes wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 6:46 am
If you're using 'right or wrong' non-morally, as 'factually correct/incorrect' seems to indicate, then presumably you mean 'true or false'. So you are really saying: 'opinions are true or false - so moral opinions are true or false'.
Yes.
But only factual assertions have truth-value. And only assertions can be objective - with public truth conditions.
Yes.
To say 'this act is morally wrong' is true or false - that this assertion of an opinion has public truth conditions and is therefore objective - merely begs the question. You're not showing that it does, you're flatly asserting that it does.
I'm not sure what question you think is being begged.

Your assumption seems to be that opinions, judgments, beliefs are not factual assertions (propositions). But they are. Calling them opinions, judgments, beliefs merely means the speaker acknowledges that he lacks conclusive evidence for the proposition, or someone else believes he doesn't. But he is still asserting a proposition, which is either true or false. E.g.:

"It is my opinion (belief, judgment) that slavery is wrong."

The embedded proposition is, "Slavery is wrong." That proposition is true or false. It is true if slavery conflicts with the axiom and postulates of the theory; it is false if slavery does not conflict with those postulates. Whether it conflicts or does not is a factual or logical matter, and is objective.

With any other subject matter this "right/wrong" would be understood as the instrumental, or factual, sense of those terms. E.g.,

"It is my opinion that we turned the wrong way at that last intersection."

The embedded proposition is, "We turned the wrong way at that last intersection." That proposition is true or false. It is true if the left turn leads away from our destination; it is false it leads toward the destination.

If the proposition embedded in the expression, judgment, belief is true (or false) then the opinion, judgment, belief is true (or false).

Moral judgments made in the context of a sound, rational moral theory are not expressions of personal values, emotional states, conditioned responses, cultural norms, or anything of the kind. They are claims that a certain act or practice is consistent or inconsistent with the axioms and theorems of that theory. Those claims are either true or false and are objective; they have public truth conditions.
And that says it all. I think our discussion has run its course. For me, at least, it's been salutary. Thanks.
Giving up so quickly? But I also enjoyed the dialogue. It has been more challenging than most here.
Not giving up, just tired of your argument.

A moral assertion such as 'slavery is wrong' is as objective as the moral axiom from which it is derived - the asserted goal or principle. And adopting an axiom is a decision which no supposed fact entails. End of story.
By GE Morton
#351603
Peter Holmes wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 2:14 pm
But P1 is false, because wanting goal Y need not entail any action X.
That is false. If Y is a goal then it does entail action. See comment to TP above, and def. of "goal."
And anyway, wanting goal Y is a matter of preference, and is therefore subjective.

The claim that we must want goal Y is a matter of opinion, and is therefore subjective.
That is true. Someone who does not share the goal for moral philosophy I cited would not be bound by the rest of the theory. Egoists, elitists, moral anarchists, et al would not be bound by it. Their conception/understanding of "morality" would bear little resemblance to that concept has it has been generally understood in the history of philosophy. The theory will be useful only to those who do share that understanding. The theorems are objective given that goal; they do or do not advance it.
#351606
GE Morton wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 2:33 pm
Peter Holmes wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 2:14 pm
But P1 is false, because wanting goal Y need not entail any action X.
That is false. If Y is a goal then it does entail action. See comment to TP above, and def. of "goal."
That is false, and TP has explained why. There's no point continuing on this issue.
And anyway, wanting goal Y is a matter of preference, and is therefore subjective.

The claim that we must want goal Y is a matter of opinion, and is therefore subjective.
That is true. Someone who does not share the goal for moral philosophy I cited would not be bound by the rest of the theory. Egoists, elitists, moral anarchists, et al would not be bound by it. Their conception/understanding of "morality" would bear little resemblance to that concept has it has been generally understood in the history of philosophy. The theory will be useful only to those who do share that understanding. The theorems are objective given that goal; they do or do not advance it.
Good. Agreement. But moral philosophers merely study moral values and issues. Your claim that there is 'the goal for moral philosophy' is false. But if there were an agreed goal, the claim that we must want that goal would be a matter of opinion, as you say. Again, end of story.
#351607
GE Morton wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 1:33 pm
Terrapin Station wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 11:00 am The big problem with it, again, is that it doesn't follow that you must or that it's better to try to achieve a goal than otherwise.
Well, I make no claim that one must try to achieve any particular goal. But if someone decides he will be better off not pursuing some goal than pursuing it, then he has abandoned that goal. It is no longer a goal for him.
The problem with this is that it's actually possible for the person to still think about it as a goal, but to feel that it's better off not pursuing that goal.

You can decide to just call it something different, but nevertheless, people can think about things that way.

Re the definition, if you asked thousands of people to tell you how they're using a term like "goal" you're actually going to get all sorts of different answers. But sure, some answers will be more common than others. That has no implication for anything else, though.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#351610
"the end toward which effort is directed"

That's not how I'd define "goal," by the way. I don't know many people who would define it that way. It would be interesting to take a few thousand people, ask them to give a definition of "goal" (where we're careful about both not giving them any context for why we're asking for the definition, and where we can ensure that they won't just look it up), and see how many actually give a definition anything like "the end toward which effort is directed."

I'd define a goal as something like, "Something I'd like to achieve, although not something I'd necessarily pursue under conditions that I don't feel are ideal for it, and where action is always tempered against other considerations."
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By GE Morton
#351647
Peter Holmes wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 2:45 pm
GE Morton wrote: March 3rd, 2020, 2:33 pm

That is false. If Y is a goal then it does entail action. See comment to TP above, and def. of "goal."
That is false, and TP has explained why. There's no point continuing on this issue.
TP's "explanation" derives from a failure to understand what a goal is, and what it implies --- namely, that one makes some efforts to secure it. If Alfie makes no efforts to secure X, then X is not a goal for him. See the dictionary definition. Are you agreeing with TP that a goal is "something in someone's head"? If not, how would you determine whether X is a goal for Alfie, other than by observing his behavior?
Your claim that there is 'the goal for moral philosophy' is false. But if there were an agreed goal, the claim that we must want that goal would be a matter of opinion, as you say. Again, end of story.
I haven't claimed that anyone "must want" that or any other goal. The theory is intended for those who think it a worthy one, and the impetus of most moral codes historically. As I said, egoists ("The right thing to do is whatever benefits me"), elitists ("The right thing do do is whatever benefits my tribe/ethnic group/social circle"), mystics ("The right thing to do is whatever the gods command, as determined by us shamans") amoralists ("If it feels good, do it") will have no use for it.
  • 1
  • 42
  • 43
  • 44
  • 45
  • 46
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


Is there something different about the transgende[…]

There is no "Rule" that can be compose[…]

Pantheism

Part of the division between protestants and catho[…]

One way to think of quantum mechanics might be tha[…]