Log In   or  Sign Up for Free

Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Club for Open-Minded Discussion & Debate

Humans-Only Club for Discussion & Debate

A one-of-a-kind oasis of intelligent, in-depth, productive, civil debate.

Topics are uncensored, meaning even extremely controversial viewpoints can be presented and argued for, but our Forum Rules strictly require all posters to stay on-topic and never engage in ad hominems or personal attacks.


Discuss morality and ethics in this message board.
Featured Article: Philosophical Analysis of Abortion, The Right to Life, and Murder
By Peter Holmes
#347969
Sculptor1 wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 4:36 am Holmes and Morton,

You seem to be off topic. Nothing you are now discussing seems to offer anything about "What could make morality objective?".
It seems to me that there can be no moral injunction which could possibly be universally understood or applicable.
Clearly what could make morality objective is the contain all moral judgement into a single entity or deity to which each human is forced to comply. This has been the rather dubious claim of the black-hooded monsters of the church since time immemorial.
When I see others claim moral objectivity all I see is a reflection of the horror of a universal church.
What? Our discussion has been smack-on-topic.

And the claim that, if moral rules came from a god (or any agent), then morality would be objective, is false. Objectivity is independence from opinion, and the opinions of a god, or any agent, can't not be opinions. If a god says 'this is morally wrong', that doesn't and can't make 'it' morally wrong - factually or objectively.

But I'm with you on the tyranny of religious institutions that falsely claim a god agrees with their moral opinions. That's the real wickedness of moral objectivism, and it's always been about power, social control and oppression.
#347981
arjand wrote: February 2nd, 2020, 7:52 pm
Terrapin Station wrote: February 2nd, 2020, 2:32 pm

What would "good" amount to where there's not a connotation of a positive valuation to it?
"good" logically cannot be valued as it is the valuing itself that is derived from the necessary ability to distinguish that it appropriates from "good".

The simple logic that something cannot give rise to itself would make it impossible to value "good" per se.
What you didn't answer is what good would amount to in your view.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#347983
GE Morton wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 12:47 am A philosophically respectable moral theory must be universal and have a rational basis.
Why would a "philosophically respectable moral theory" have requirements that can not be met?
When I said morality "isn't about values," I meant it does not assume, or prescribe, any particular values. It does acknowledge, however, that people value various things and that their quality of life is largely determined by the extent to which those values are realized. It assumes that everyone desires to maximize his/her quality of life.
This sounds like you're talking exclusively about metaethics? Sticking to just a descriptive account of what morality is, how it works, etc.?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#347984
Peter Holmes wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 4:14 am Agreed, value-judgements are subjective, by definition. But they can be, and usually are, perfectly rational.
Maybe you're using "rational" in a different way than I would? Otherwise I don't know how you'd be figuring that value judgments are rational.
The reciprocity essential for the existence of higher primate groups is there at the foundation of our morality.
So for example, re me being stumped at you thinking that values are rational, one has to care about (that is, value) the existence of "higher primate groups" to think that the existence of higher primate groups is better than the non-existence of higher primate groups. You'd have to claim something like "caring about continued existence is more rational" but I don't know how you'd get there. It doesn't seem to have anything to do with rationality. It seems to hinge on valuing existence.
particularly acts that adversely affect other moral agents, which reduce their welfare or prevent them from improving it.
(a) One has to value not adversely affecting other moral agents . . . there's not a rational way to get to "it's better to not adversely affect other moral agents" without valuing something at the start.

(b) what people consider to adversely affect them rather than 'improving' them is subjective and value-based, not rationally-based.
Whether an particular act does or does not have that effect is objectively determinable
Only per an individual, only once that individual shares their values, their desires.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
User avatar
By psyreporter
#347990
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 9:06 am
arjand wrote: February 2nd, 2020, 7:52 pm "good" logically cannot be valued as it is the valuing itself that is derived from the necessary ability to distinguish that it appropriates from "good".

The simple logic that something cannot give rise to itself would make it impossible to value "good" per se.
What you didn't answer is what good would amount to in your view.
By the cited logic "good" cannot be valued as the valuing itself is essentially an appropriation of "good" and something cannot give rise to itself.

"good" must be real because otherwise valuing could not be possible.
User avatar
By psyreporter
#347992
Thomyum2 wrote: February 2nd, 2020, 11:56 am So I think I understand what @arjand is getting at here (he/she will maybe correct me if I'm mistaken). When we talk about the 'good' of something, we're meaning more than just a temporary satisfaction of a desire or value - we're referring our sense of to an understood or imagined state of affairs that is good. In other words, there's a sense of the idea of 'good' that precedes the assignment of desire or value - it is the fixed idea or goal beyond the object itself.
The indicated "good" doesn't need to be sensible. It could be imply able. It is implied to be real but not visible in the empirical (sensible) reality. A living being could translate it to emotions and senses.
Thomyum2 wrote: February 2nd, 2020, 11:56 amOur pursuit of specific goals may change and evolve over time, yet the idea of good is one that we understand that we may recognize when we find it, and may recognize it differently from one individual to the next, but that it is not good simply because we as an individual have chosen it and made the efforts to bring it about.
In my opinion, valuing by an individual is an appropriation of "good". The "good" is real but there is an aspect involved that, while it is not a pure mental opinion, is biased in such that it is relative to the individual only, whom cannot precede that what it derives the ability to value from. Thus, a desire, a will to survive, a strive to prevent pain etc, are much heavier than a mere mental opinion but it involves a relatively to an individual that cannot precede that from which it derives its ability to value, and whom thereby cannot define his/her values as a "fact" by the standards of empirical science.
Thomyum2 wrote: February 2nd, 2020, 11:56 am I also think that as social beings, we all understand that any idea of the 'good' has an element of a quality that is common to all. The word functions in language similarly to the word 'true' in that we may disagree about what is or is not 'true', but our definition is such that it has an objective meaning to it. Things are not 'true' or 'good' merely because an individual 'assigns' that quality to them, but rather because they correspond to an idea of a truth or goodness that is shared with others. So in a roundabout way, I guess the bottom of my point is that say that although we all make judgments of what is good, just as we do of what is true, we can't make these judgments in isolation as individuals, but must make them as a shared understanding.

Your thoughts?
Yes, I would agree. It would be a task for philosophy to structurize a correct appropriation of "good" to evolve beyond religions and atheistic (dogmatic) empirical science.
User avatar
By Sculptor1
#347994
Peter Holmes wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 5:18 am
Sculptor1 wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 4:36 am Holmes and Morton,

You seem to be off topic. Nothing you are now discussing seems to offer anything about "What could make morality objective?".
It seems to me that there can be no moral injunction which could possibly be universally understood or applicable.
Clearly what could make morality objective is the contain all moral judgement into a single entity or deity to which each human is forced to comply. This has been the rather dubious claim of the black-hooded monsters of the church since time immemorial.
When I see others claim moral objectivity all I see is a reflection of the horror of a universal church.
What? Our discussion has been smack-on-topic.

And the claim that, if moral rules came from a god (or any agent), then morality would be objective, is false. Objectivity is independence from opinion, and the opinions of a god, or any agent, can't not be opinions. If a god says 'this is morally wrong', that doesn't and can't make 'it' morally wrong - factually or objectively.

But I'm with you on the tyranny of religious institutions that falsely claim a god agrees with their moral opinions. That's the real wickedness of moral objectivism, and it's always been about power, social control and oppression.
And it is precisely this fact coupled with the fact that tyrannous religious in defining what god is precisely make my point which you disagree with. Definitively God has no opinion.

Aside from that there is simply NO prospect of morality being objective IN ANY SENSE.
In other words there is no prospect of morality being objective in no sense but nonsense.
Any attempt to make it so is nothing more or less than tyranny of opinion.
User avatar
By Sculptor1
#347995
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 9:21 am
Peter Holmes wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 4:14 am Agreed, value-judgements are subjective, by definition. But they can be, and usually are, perfectly rational.
Maybe you're using "rational" in a different way than I would? Otherwise I don't know how you'd be figuring that value judgments are rational.
This is a no-brainer.
We are all perfectly capable of forming opinions rationally. It make little difference if such positions are objective or subjective as this does not bear upon their rationality.

By contrast it might be possible to state an objective fact but can be completely irrational to do so.
By GE Morton
#347996
Peter Holmes wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 4:14 am
GE Morton wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 12:47 am
Very often we are. But those value judgments are subjective and have no rational basis. A philosophically respectable moral theory must be universal and have a rational basis.
Agreed, value-judgements are subjective, by definition. But they can be, and usually are, perfectly rational. It's their rationality that has resulted in social moral codes, often with universal scope, and often reinforced by law.

In response to your assertion, "When we say 'this action is morally good or bad, right or wrong', we're making a value-judgement," I said, "Very often we are." "Vernacular moralities" --- the moral precepts accepted and applied by most people --- are indeed often based on subjective values. They are absorbed unexamined through religious indoctrination, cultural conditioning, or simply reflect personal interests, preferences, emotional responses, i.e., personal values. And values are non-rational by definition.
Why identify subjectivity with irrationality? How strange
I don't. Those are different properties. Values are not irrational; they're non-rational (true of values assigned to "end goods." Values assigned to "means goods" can be rational). And because they are also subjective moral principles based on them cannot be universal.
And the very idea of a 'philosophically respectable moral theory' needs unpacking. What we need is an explanation or description of morality that makes rationally justified claims derived from sound arguments. If that's what you mean - I agree.
Yes, that is what I mean. It should be obvious that a morality based on values cannot possibly satisfy that criterion.
And I agree that description isn't prescription, in moral as in any other discourse. But the question 'what is morally right and wrong?' is central to both moral and ethical theory. And it goes beyond and deeper than a description of what people want and say about it.
Well, if so, then those depths need to be explored. But in my view, to say that some act was morally wrong merely means that it violates one or more theorems of a sound moral theory, the theorems of which impose duties or constraints on the actions of moral agents in a social setting.
My point is that value-judgements and facts are completely different things, so that nothing can make morality objective.
A moral judgment --- a rationally defensible one --- is not a value judgment. That mistake reveals why it is important not to confuse deontology with axiology. "That painting is not worth what Alfie paid or it" is a value judgment. "It was (morally) wrong for Alfie to beat his wife" is not. The latter asserts that Alfie's act violated a sound moral principle. That it did so is a matter of fact.

We do, of course, assign positive value to morally acceptable acts (they're "good") and negative value to unacceptable ones ("bad"). But that valuation has nothing to do with the soundness of the principles applied in judging those acts.
Morality is about what is morally right or wrong. Moral assertions, expressing moral judgements, contain words like 'right', 'wrong', 'good', 'bad', 'should' and 'ought'. But commands such as 'do not kill' aren't even declaratives, let alone moral declaratives. The morally significant (operative or functional) claim is 'it is wrong to kill'. 'Do and don't' commands - and, more important, simply obeying them, are morally insignificant, in the sense that the moral questions are taken as having been settled. (Of course, you're right about the practical consequences of different codes and rules.)
That is a verbal quibble. "One ought not kill" implies, "Do not kill." The declarative entails the imperative. But I agree that merely following a rule, any rule, blindly, without understanding its rationale, merits no moral praise.
By GE Morton
#348000
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 9:11 am
GE Morton wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 12:47 am A philosophically respectable moral theory must be universal and have a rational basis.
Why would a "philosophically respectable moral theory" have requirements that can not be met?
Oh, they can be met. But if they could not then morality would not be within the purview of philosophy.
This sounds like you're talking exclusively about metaethics? Sticking to just a descriptive account of what morality is, how it works, etc.?
Yes. Various metaethical questions need to be answered before ethics can be productively pursued.
By GE Morton
#348001
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 9:21 am
(a) One has to value not adversely affecting other moral agents . . . there's not a rational way to get to "it's better to not adversely affect other moral agents" without valuing something at the start.
It is true that one must value something in order to perceive any need for moral principles. The entire aim of morality is to enhance the ability of moral agents to secure the things they value. But an agent need not value other agents in order to assent to those principles. He will assent because he perceives that compliance is in his own best interests.
(b) what people consider to adversely affect them rather than 'improving' them is subjective and value-based, not rationally-based.
Oh, no. A claim often asserted, but easily dismissed. Alfie owns a bicycle, for which he spent a month's pay. We know that Alfie values the bicycle, because he has invested time and effort to acquire it. That he has made that investment tells us that the bicycle contributes to his well-being. Then Bruno steals the bicycle. Given the above, Bruno has reduced Alfie's well-being. That latter proposition is objective, a "fact."
User avatar
By psyreporter
#348013
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 9:06 amWhat you didn't answer is what good would amount to in your view.
The "good" that is indicated is empirically incomprehensible as it precedes the tangible reality. My argument is that "good" may be imply-ably comprehensible.

"good" cannot be assigned a value as valuing itself is derived from the necessary ability to distinguish, which is appropriated from "good". It means that "good" cannot amount to anything empirically. It precedes the senses.
#348015
arjand wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 4:31 pm
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 9:06 amWhat you didn't answer is what good would amount to in your view.
The "good" that is indicated is empirically incomprehensible as it precedes the tangible reality. My argument is that "good" may be imply-ably comprehensible.
What in the world are you talking about? So you're talking about something you're calling "good" that's incomprehensible?
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
#348016
GE Morton wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 12:59 pm
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 9:21 am
(a) One has to value not adversely affecting other moral agents . . . there's not a rational way to get to "it's better to not adversely affect other moral agents" without valuing something at the start.
It is true that one must value something in order to perceive any need for moral principles. The entire aim of morality is to enhance the ability of moral agents to secure the things they value. But an agent need not value other agents in order to assent to those principles. He will assent because he perceives that compliance is in his own best interests.
?? The comment I wrote was in response to someone talking about other moral agents. I wasn't making an out-of-context generalization.It was a response to that specific comment.
(b) what people consider to adversely affect them rather than 'improving' them is subjective and value-based, not rationally-based.
Oh, no. A claim often asserted, but easily dismissed. Alfie owns a bicycle, for which he spent a month's pay. We know that Alfie values the bicycle, because he has invested time and effort to acquire it. That he has made that investment tells us that the bicycle contributes to his well-being. Then Bruno steals the bicycle. Given the above, Bruno has reduced Alfie's well-being. That latter proposition is objective, a "fact."
[/quote]

It's based on what Alfie values, which isn't objective.
Favorite Philosopher: Bertrand Russell and WVO Quine Location: NYC Man
By GE Morton
#348038
Terrapin Station wrote: February 3rd, 2020, 4:42 pm
It's based on what Alfie values, which isn't objective.
No it is not. It is based on the fact that Alfie values the bicycle.

This is a surprisingly hard point to get across.

We don't care what Alfie values or why he values it, which are indeed subjective. But we know that he does value certain things, and that those things contribute to his quality of life. Those are objective facts.
  • 1
  • 13
  • 14
  • 15
  • 16
  • 17
  • 143

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II

On Spirits: The World Hidden Volume II
by Dr. Joseph M. Feagan
April 2025

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)

Escape to Paradise and Beyond (Tentative)
by Maitreya Dasa
March 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking for Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science

Connecting the Dots: Ancient Wisdom, Modern Science
by Lia Russ
December 2024

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


The people I've known whom I see as good peopl[…]

This quote was added after I'd posted this note. B[…]