- January 5th, 2020, 5:23 pm
#344809
Thomas goes on to say that although his way of describing a morally defensible view is compatible with severe differences on important moral issues, the account is far from empty. It may not settle the moral status of abortion, but it can tell us that American chattel slavery and the Holocaust must be wrong. Slavery is wrong because the slave owners kept black women as mistresses, their wives were jealous, the slaves nursed white children and cared for those children, sexual relations between slave and master produced fertile offspring, and slaves and masters spoke the same language- all this is evidence that slave owners could not deny that they believed that blacks are fully human- based on the evidence at hand, no one could reasonably deny that blacks are fully human. The same can be said of Jews- it was not possible to deny that Jews are fully human, says Thomas.
Now, says Thomas, lets go back to our consideration of Socrates, Lincoln and King regarding slavery. Because of context in which Socrates lived, it is not possible to make a negative judgement about his views regarding slavery. But for King, considering the historical context, to accept slavery would be inexcusable. It is also the case that Socrates did not believe slaves must be black. Socrates also did not assert that slaves lacked the mental and moral features of free people. The myth surrounding Lincoln is that he rose above his own personal beliefs and did what he thought was right for the United States. The reality, say Thomas, is that Lincoln did believe that blacks were naturally inferior to whites- and yet he agonized over the justification of slavery, while retaining his belief that blacks are inferior to whites.
Thomas notes that there is a difference between believing that blacks are fully human and believing that blacks are inferior to whites. "Whatever people may have been justified in believing about the intellectual abilities of blacks, they were never... justified in believing that blacks were less than fully human beings".
Thomas mentioned that one defining characteristic of persons of good moral character is the defensibility of their moral views- he also mentioned another feature- that of an altruistic character. Thomas invokes Aristotle here- "Aristotle remarked that the virtuous person is one who does the right thing, at the right time, in the right manner, toward the right objects..." Thomas will offer a sustained defense of his (Thomas') view of the altruistic nature in Chapter 2.
The other defining feature that Thomas wants to discuss is moral autonomy. Morally autonomous people are concerned with doing the right things for the right reasons- they want to be able to give reasons to justify their moral views-they don't appeal to popularity or arguments from authority. They have a deep conviction, not tied to obedience to any authority. Thomas argues that they are morally independent in thought and action.
Thomas contrasts the view of the morally autonomous with that of what he calls the morally nonautonomous. Morally nonautonomous people hold that right behavior is a matter of duty, obedience and upholding social order. Their views are strongly influenced by that of social institutions. They want their views to be socially acceptable- and if enough people disapprove, they will change their views. The nonautonomous, says Thomas are not concerned with being able to justify their beliefs and actions with reason- they are not concerned with doing what is right for the right reasons. The example that Thomas uses is that of a religious person who unquestioningly accepts the teaching of her religion- she might even take pride in her ability to accept her pastor's biblical interpretations.
The morally autonomous take the time to critically examine their own views, and even "revise then in light of newly perceived weaknesses and strengths". Because of this, the views of the morally autonomous change even while the views of the culture around them does not. Thomas argues that while everyone is influenced by their culture, the morally autonomous question the influence of that culture while the morally autonomous do not.
Thomas points out that in many areas morally autonomous and morally nonautonomous do agree (for instance, both groups probably accept that to kill innocent people is wrong). But, the views of the autonomous change as they reflect on the need for revision, while the nonautonomous fail to see this to change.
Here Thomas goes back to the religious. Some might argue that because religious fundamentalists are impervious to public opinion, they qualify as being morally autonomous- some fundamentalists do refrain from dancing and going to movies, after all, even though the majority around them think it's silly to hold those views. But, they should not be considered to be morally autonomous because they are bound to uncritically accept what their church teaches. They believe that God requires this behavior of them, and that God will punish them if they refuse. Their convictions, says Thomas are based on their belief that they will be punished if they don't comply. Ultimately, it's a fear of authority. It's not standing fast in one's convictions that determines moral autonomy, it's the reason for those convictions that matters.