Philosophy Discussion Forums | A Humans-Only Philosophy Club

Philosophy Discussion Forums
A Humans-Only Philosophy Club

The Philosophy Forums at OnlinePhilosophyClub.com aim to be an oasis of intelligent in-depth civil debate and discussion. Topics discussed extend far beyond philosophy and philosophers. What makes us a philosophy forum is more about our approach to the discussions than what subject is being debated. Common topics include but are absolutely not limited to neuroscience, psychology, sociology, cosmology, religion, political theory, ethics, and so much more.

This is a humans-only philosophy club. We strictly prohibit bots and AIs from joining.


Discuss any topics related to metaphysics (the philosophical study of the principles of reality) or epistemology (the philosophical study of knowledge) in this forum.
User avatar
By Consul
#331868
GaryLouisSmith wrote: June 4th, 2019, 9:08 pm Consul wrote," Right, but materialism/physicalism isn't wedded to any particular fundamental ontology. For example, it is compatible with process ontology, with trope ontology, and with nominalism about attributes (properties).

Materialism is the belief that there is an underlying material substance that endures or perdures through change. Attributes or Forms are fleeting but matter remains. Materialism is a substance philosophy. If the Nominalism and Tropism and Process philosophy you are thinking of are also substance philosophies, then, Yes, they are compatible with materialism, if not then no. I think most people on this blog believe in matter as an underlying substance. I don’t. Berkeley effectively destroyed the idea of matter as substance.
I don't think so; but, anyway, by trope (trope-field) ontology or event/process ontology I mean a basic ontology in which substances (or objects or things) are not a basic, irreducible ontological category. They are either eliminated altogether or reduced to complexes of tropes or events/processes. Modern materialism qua physicalism is compatible with those anti-substance ontologies as well.
Location: Germany
By GaryLouisSmith
#331869
Consul wrote: June 5th, 2019, 3:33 am

I don't think so; but, anyway, by trope (trope-field) ontology or event/process ontology I mean a basic ontology in which substances (or objects or things) are not a basic, irreducible ontological category. They are either eliminated altogether or reduced to complexes of tropes or events/processes. Modern materialism qua physicalism is compatible with those anti-substance ontologies as well.
You may well be right about that; I cannot say because I am not all that familiar with trope-field ontology or process ontology. I do know what a trope is, however. And I know the bundle theory of objects. I consider that nominalism. I am curious as to what you think are the basic, irreducible ontological categories. If you are interested I could tell you what I think they are. Are you a physicalist/materialist? Do you think the ontology of time can be done without substance? I personally think that time is too difficult an ontologicval problem for the human mind. Substance doesn't work, but what else there is ... beats me.
Favorite Philosopher: Gustav Bergmann Location: Kathmandu, Nepal
User avatar
By Consul
#331870
GaryLouisSmith wrote: June 4th, 2019, 9:08 pm Consul wrote," Right, but materialism/physicalism isn't wedded to any particular fundamental ontology. For example, it is compatible with process ontology, with trope ontology, and with nominalism about attributes (properties).

Materialism is the belief that there is an underlying material substance that endures or perdures through change. Attributes or Forms are fleeting but matter remains. Materialism is a substance philosophy. If the Nominalism…
As for nominalism defined as general/universal antirealism about attributes/properties, be they universals or particulars: It is compatible both with substance (thing) ontology and with process (event) ontology.
For example, Tadeusz Kotarbinski's materialistic reism (which he called pansomatism) is antirealistic about properties, but it's a version of substance ontology: Everything is a thing, and every thing is a body.
Location: Germany
By GaryLouisSmith
#331871
Consul wrote: June 5th, 2019, 3:47 am
As for nominalism defined as general/universal antirealism about attributes/properties, be they universals or particulars: It is compatible both with substance (thing) ontology and with process (event) ontology.
For example, Tadeusz Kotarbinski is antirealistic about properties, but it's a version of substance ontology: Everything is a thing, and every thing is a body.
All those things that Brentano called irrealia or entia rationis, things which he put in the mind, I say are things that exist external to the mind. Moreover, (hang on to your chair) all those “syncategorical” unthings, aka internal properties. are things I deify. I make them gods. A god is something that when you contemplate it, it becomes a frisson up your back. A shiver. Jimjam.

To tell the truth I think Brentano thought of irrealia as such. They were ghosts, Nervenkitzel. There is something enchanted about them. Metaphysical in the sense of creepy otherworldly things.

I like Kotarbinski’s word “onomatoid” which refers to all those things Brentano called irrealia. It’s a creepy word, it names ontological beasties, otherworldly unthings. Things that are not real. The logic is marvelous. Like Brentano, I think Tadeusz Katarbinski was a dark mystic. That makes him one of the good guys in my book.
Favorite Philosopher: Gustav Bergmann Location: Kathmandu, Nepal
By Tamminen
#331873
Tamminen wrote: June 5th, 2019, 2:30 am Even Kant's "thing in itself" has an ontological relationship with the subject although we cannot say anything of it.
It seems that with the concept of 'noumenon' Kant suggested the possibility of genuine transcendence. But as I said, I think that the only rational concept of transcendence is transcendence in relation to immanence, subjectivity: transcendence of knowing, not transcendence of being.
By Atla
#331879
Consul wrote: June 4th, 2019, 3:36 pm
Atla wrote: June 4th, 2019, 2:30 pmI think you don't understand what phenomenal consciousness (and the hard problem of consciousness) refer to so you may have misunderstood all my posts.
You're wrong, because I know very well both what phenomenal consciousness is and what the "hard problem" or "explanatory gap" is.
If you would, you would understand that materialism by definition can't solve the explanatory gap, as I explained. Then maybe you could get out of this trap that you are in.

That's why it is that even though we've mapped the correlations between "mental events" and "material events" to a remarkable degree, there has never been any progress on the explanatory gap.
User avatar
By Consul
#331880
Atla wrote: June 5th, 2019, 11:07 amIf you would, you would understand that materialism by definition can't solve the explanatory gap, as I explained. Then maybe you could get out of this trap that you are in.
That's why it is that even though we've mapped the correlations between "mental events" and "material events" to a remarkable degree, there has never been any progress on the explanatory gap.
You're wrong insofar as it is by no means impossible by definition for (materialistic) neuroscience to solve the hard problem and to close the explanatory gap.

You're right insofar as mere psychophysical correlations aren't explanatory. We want an explanation of those correlations, so what the neuroscience of consciousness (NSC) must discover in the CNS aren't only the neural correlates of consciousness but also the constitutive neural mechanisms of consciousness. For these are explanatory, making neuroreductive explanations of conscious/experiential events/states possible.

Generally, such mechanistic explanations have both "piercing explanatory power" and "ontologically unifying power" (C. Gillett); and if they are available in NSC —which is not yet the case—, they thereby provide a scientific vindication of the materialist assumption that phenomenal consciousness or what Antti Revonsuo calls "the phenomenal level of organization in the brain" is a purely neurological or physicochemical process, such that the neural mechanisms of consciousness are justifiedly identifiable with consciousness itself: NMC = C

"According to biological realism, the primary target is to find neural phenomena in the brain that go beyond mere correlative relationships with consciousness. The relationship between the phenomenal level and the lower neural levels is not correlation but hierarchical constitution. The phenomena at the lower neural levels constitute the higher phenomenal level. Thus, what neuroscience should be looking for, it if aims at discovering ad explaining consciousness, are the constitutive mechanisms of consciousness (CMC), rather than just the NCC."

(Revonsuo, Antti. Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006. p. 297)

"Constitutive Explanation
Constitutive explanation involves moving downward in the hierarchy and looking at a smaller-scale spatiotemporal grain or a lower level of organization. It is accomplished by showing that the phenomenon appearing as an integrated whole at one level can be decomposed to its constituent parts and their causal interactions at the immediately underlying, lower levels of description. Constitutive explanations describe the lower-level mechanisms that the entity is composed of, or whose activity, when taken as a whole, simply is the phenomenon to be explained by the description of the mechanism.

An illuminating example from biology is the cell. A single cell, taken as a whole, is an independent living unit. The constitutive explanation revealing what makes the cell tick descends to the immediately lower levels of organization where the different parts of the cell and their causal interactions are to be found.

When the same strategy is applied to the explanation of consciousness there is, first of all, the phenomenon to be explained (the explanandum): consciousness. It resides at some specific level of organization in the brain (the phenomenal level). The lower-level, nonconscious neurophysiological mechanisms, whose activity as a whole constitutes consciousness, reside at a lower level of organization in the brain.

The current search for the direct NCC appears to be the empirical approach to the constitutive explanation of consciousness. However, the notion 'neural correlates of consciousness' requires considerable clarification. The relationship between an explanandum and its lower-level constituents must be stronger than mere correlation, for correlation is not an explanatory relationship. The cell membrane, the nucleus, chromosomes, cell organelles, and other microscopic parts of the cell are not merely the biological correlates of life, but crucial microlevel constituents that explain why the whole system is alive. In the same vein, the constitutive explanation of consciousness should describe such part-whole or mereological relationships between the lower- and higher-level phenomena that make their hierarchical connection truly explanatory."


(Revonsuo, Antti. Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006. pp. 18-20)

"Perhaps most famously, across the sciences we find explanations that explain higher-level entities (whether individuals, properties, or processes) in terms of lower-level entities that scientists take to compose them and hence these explanations use vertical relations. For example, we explain the inheritance of traits between parent organisms and their off spring using molecules taken to compose them. We explain the refractive index of a crystal using the properties and relations of the atoms that compose it. Or we explain the movement of the earth’s surface using the tectonic plates, and currents of magma, taken to compose the earth. We use the term 'compositional explanation' to refer to such explanation, though philosophers have used various names for it.(3 And we term the vertical relations that such explanations posit 'scientific composition' relations where this includes relations between individuals, properties/relations, and also processes.
(3 Other terms include 'reductive explanation', 'microstructural analyses', 'functional explanation', 'constitutive explanation', or 'mechanistic explanation'.)"


(Aizawa, Kenneth, and Carl Gillett. "Introduction: Vertical Relations in Science, Philosophy, and the World: Understanding the New Debates over Verticality." In Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground, edited by Kenneth Aizawa and Carl Gillett, 1-38. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016. p. 2)

"The Scientific Revolution was powered, at least in large part, by explanations that pierced the manifest image of common sense by explaining its level of everyday individuals, properties, and processes using qualitatively distinct, lower-level entities taken to compose them. And such explanations have now been iterated through all the levels of nature. For example, we take the corrosive action of glaciers to be explained by the movement of the ice molecules that we take to compose glaciers. We explain the motility of cells using the properties and relations of the molecules that we take to compose them. We understand why kidneys clean blood in terms of the properties and relations of the cells taken to compose them. And we could easily go on, and on, through such explanations across the sciences. Given their nature, such explanations are plausibly termed 'compositional' explanations, since they are founded around showing how lower-level entities of one kind (whether individuals, properties, or processes) compose entities of very different kinds at higher levels. Philosophers of science have used a range of other terms for compositional explanation, including 'reductive explanation', 'functional explanation', or 'mechanistic explanation', and there is a substantial body of work on the nature of such explanation, including a recent burst of research. Oddly, however, a couple of the key features of compositional explanations have not received much philosophical attention.

First, compositional explanations allow us to explain one kind of entity, such as a cell or its moving, in terms of the qualitatively different kinds of entity taken to compose it, like molecules or molecular processes of polymerization, and this hence results in what I term the 'Piercing Explanatory Power', or 'PEP', of compositional explanations. Second, we should mark that once we have successfully supplied a compositional explanation of certain entities in terms of certain others that compose them, then we have established that these entities are in some sense the same. Most importantly, a successful compositional explanation consequently shows that the mass-energy, or force, associated with a certain entity just is the mass-energy, or force, of certain component entities. This is what I will term the 'Ontologically Unifying Power', or 'OUP', of compositional explanations.

Our vast array of compositional explanations in the sciences, from fundamental physics to condensed matter physics or materials sciences, on to chemistry or biochemistry, through cytology and physiology, and now even beginning to encompass the neurosciences and psychology have had intellectual impacts in all kinds of ways. For instance, compositional explanations have been central to the centuries-old unification project in physics that has now established that there are no special forces, or energies, and that the only fundamental forces and energies are all microphysical in character. Connected to the later finding, and again driven by compositional explanations, working scientists now routinely assume the global claim that everything in nature is either identical to a microphysical entity or is composed by microphysical entities. (I will call this thesis 'physicalism' here.)"


(Gillett, Carl. "The Metaphysics of Nature, Science, and the Rules of Engagement." In Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground, edited by Kenneth Aizawa and Carl Gillett, 205-247. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016. pp. 205-7)
Location: Germany
By Atla
#331881
Consul wrote: June 5th, 2019, 12:05 pm You're wrong insofar as it is by no means impossible by definition for (materialistic) neuroscience to solve the hard problem and to close the explanatory gap. You're wrong insofar as it is by no means impossible by definition for (materialistic) neuroscience to solve the hard problem and to close the explanatory gap.
I'm not wrong, it's impossible by definition.
You're right insofar as mere psychophysical correlations aren't explanatory. We want an explanation of those correlations, so what the neuroscience of consciousness (NSC) must discover in the CNS aren't only the neural correlates of consciousness but also the constitutive neural mechanisms of consciousness. For these are explanatory, making neuroreductive explanations of conscious/experiential events/states possible.

Generally, such mechanistic explanations have both "piercing explanatory power" and "ontologically unifying power" (C. Gillett); and if they are available in NSC —which is not yet the case—, they thereby provide a scientific vindication of the materialist assumption that phenomenal consciousness or what Antti Revonsuo calls "the phenomenal level of organization in the brain" is a purely neurological or physicochemical process, such that the neural mechanisms of consciousness are justifiedly identifiable with consciousness itself: NMC = C

"According to biological realism, the primary target is to find neural phenomena in the brain that go beyond mere correlative relationships with consciousness. The relationship between the phenomenal level and the lower neural levels is not correlation but hierarchical constitution. The phenomena at the lower neural levels constitute the higher phenomenal level. Thus, what neuroscience should be looking for, it if aims at discovering ad explaining consciousness, are the constitutive mechanisms of consciousness (CMC), rather than just the NCC."

(Revonsuo, Antti. Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006. p. 297)

"Constitutive Explanation
Constitutive explanation involves moving downward in the hierarchy and looking at a smaller-scale spatiotemporal grain or a lower level of organization. It is accomplished by showing that the phenomenon appearing as an integrated whole at one level can be decomposed to its constituent parts and their causal interactions at the immediately underlying, lower levels of description. Constitutive explanations describe the lower-level mechanisms that the entity is composed of, or whose activity, when taken as a whole, simply is the phenomenon to be explained by the description of the mechanism.

An illuminating example from biology is the cell. A single cell, taken as a whole, is an independent living unit. The constitutive explanation revealing what makes the cell tick descends to the immediately lower levels of organization where the different parts of the cell and their causal interactions are to be found.

When the same strategy is applied to the explanation of consciousness there is, first of all, the phenomenon to be explained (the explanandum): consciousness. It resides at some specific level of organization in the brain (the phenomenal level). The lower-level, nonconscious neurophysiological mechanisms, whose activity as a whole constitutes consciousness, reside at a lower level of organization in the brain.

The current search for the direct NCC appears to be the empirical approach to the constitutive explanation of consciousness. However, the notion 'neural correlates of consciousness' requires considerable clarification. The relationship between an explanandum and its lower-level constituents must be stronger than mere correlation, for correlation is not an explanatory relationship. The cell membrane, the nucleus, chromosomes, cell organelles, and other microscopic parts of the cell are not merely the biological correlates of life, but crucial microlevel constituents that explain why the whole system is alive. In the same vein, the constitutive explanation of consciousness should describe such part-whole or mereological relationships between the lower- and higher-level phenomena that make their hierarchical connection truly explanatory."

(Revonsuo, Antti. Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006. pp. 18-20)

"Perhaps most famously, across the sciences we find explanations that explain higher-level entities (whether individuals, properties, or processes) in terms of lower-level entities that scientists take to compose them and hence these explanations use vertical relations. For example, we explain the inheritance of traits between parent organisms and their off spring using molecules taken to compose them. We explain the refractive index of a crystal using the properties and relations of the atoms that compose it. Or we explain the movement of the earth’s surface using the tectonic plates, and currents of magma, taken to compose the earth. We use the term 'compositional explanation' to refer to such explanation, though philosophers have used various names for it.(3 And we term the vertical relations that such explanations posit 'scientific composition' relations where this includes relations between individuals, properties/relations, and also processes.
(3 Other terms include 'reductive explanation', 'microstructural analyses', 'functional explanation', 'constitutive explanation', or 'mechanistic explanation'.)"

(Aizawa, Kenneth, and Carl Gillett. "Introduction: Vertical Relations in Science, Philosophy, and the World: Understanding the New Debates over Verticality." In Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground, edited by Kenneth Aizawa and Carl Gillett, 1-38. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016. p. 2)

"The Scientific Revolution was powered, at least in large part, by explanations that pierced the manifest image of common sense by explaining its level of everyday individuals, properties, and processes using qualitatively distinct, lower-level entities taken to compose them. And such explanations have now been iterated through all the levels of nature. For example, we take the corrosive action of glaciers to be explained by the movement of the ice molecules that we take to compose glaciers. We explain the motility of cells using the properties and relations of the molecules that we take to compose them. We understand why kidneys clean blood in terms of the properties and relations of the cells taken to compose them. And we could easily go on, and on, through such explanations across the sciences. Given their nature, such explanations are plausibly termed 'compositional' explanations, since they are founded around showing how lower-level entities of one kind (whether individuals, properties, or processes) compose entities of very different kinds at higher levels. Philosophers of science have used a range of other terms for compositional explanation, including 'reductive explanation', 'functional explanation', or 'mechanistic explanation', and there is a substantial body of work on the nature of such explanation, including a recent burst of research. Oddly, however, a couple of the key features of compositional explanations have not received much philosophical attention.

First, compositional explanations allow us to explain one kind of entity, such as a cell or its moving, in terms of the qualitatively different kinds of entity taken to compose it, like molecules or molecular processes of polymerization, and this hence results in what I term the 'Piercing Explanatory Power', or 'PEP', of compositional explanations. Second, we should mark that once we have successfully supplied a compositional explanation of certain entities in terms of certain others that compose them, then we have established that these entities are in some sense the same. Most importantly, a successful compositional explanation consequently shows that the mass-energy, or force, associated with a certain entity just is the mass-energy, or force, of certain component entities. This is what I will term the 'Ontologically Unifying Power', or 'OUP', of compositional explanations.

Our vast array of compositional explanations in the sciences, from fundamental physics to condensed matter physics or materials sciences, on to chemistry or biochemistry, through cytology and physiology, and now even beginning to encompass the neurosciences and psychology have had intellectual impacts in all kinds of ways. For instance, compositional explanations have been central to the centuries-old unification project in physics that has now established that there are no special forces, or energies, and that the only fundamental forces and energies are all microphysical in character. Connected to the later finding, and again driven by compositional explanations, working scientists now routinely assume the global claim that everything in nature is either identical to a microphysical entity or is composed by microphysical entities. (I will call this thesis 'physicalism' here.)"

(Gillett, Carl. "The Metaphysics of Nature, Science, and the Rules of Engagement." In Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground, edited by Kenneth Aizawa and Carl Gillett, 205-247. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016. pp. 205-7)
Endless wishful thinking, epicycling. Phenomenal consciousness has no known "constitutive neural mechanisms". Nothing of the sort was ever found, obviously (which is necessary so by definition).
User avatar
By Consul
#331883
Atla wrote: June 5th, 2019, 12:27 pm
Consul wrote: June 5th, 2019, 12:05 pm You're wrong insofar as it is by no means impossible by definition for (materialistic) neuroscience to solve the hard problem and to close the explanatory gap. You're wrong insofar as it is by no means impossible by definition for (materialistic) neuroscience to solve the hard problem and to close the explanatory gap.
I'm not wrong, it's impossible by definition.
By which definition?
Atla wrote: June 5th, 2019, 12:27 pmEndless wishful thinking, epicycling. Phenomenal consciousness has no known "constitutive neural mechanisms". Nothing of the sort was ever found, obviously (which is necessary so by definition).
By far, the most plausible and most defensible assumption is that the brain is the organ of consciousness, and that the field/stream or state of consciousness with its experiential contents is constituted or realized by and in the brain through extremely complex neurological mechanisms.

"The human brain is the most complex entity we know of. It contains at least 90 billion neurons (nerve cells). Each of these is a complex information-processing device in its own right and interacts with about 1,000 other neurons. Understanding this degree of complexity is a daunting task."

(Seth, Anil, ed. 30-Second Brain. London: Icon Books, 2017. p. 6)

As I already said, the neuroscience of consciousness is a new, 21st-century science that is still in its infancy. There couldn't have been such a science before Santiago Ramón y Cajal's revolutionary discoveries at the end of the 19th century:

"Acknowledged by many to be the architect of modern neurobiology, as a young man Cajal tried very hard to keep out of medicine altogether. He wanted to be an artist, but his father (a professor of dissection) was equally adamant that he should be a doctor. After miserable but educational apprenticeships with a cobbler and a barber, Cajal gained his medical licence and buckled down to join the family business, eventually being appointed Professor of Anatomy at Valencia.

He kept up with his drawing, making many anatomical studies, and it is possible that it was his artistic eye that led him to his greatest discovery. When in 1887, now at the University of Barcelona, he looked at the Italian physician Camillo Golgi’s immaculately stained slides of brain cells, he saw what others had not. Until this time, the prevailing orthodoxy was that the nervous system was a single reticular (mesh-like) construct without discrete cellular components (neurons). Cajal realized however that what Golgi’s images clearly showed was that the nervous system was a network of discrete cellular components. This was a correct interpretation that crucially allowed neurons to be regarded as the functional „units of the brain – free agents that could form many synaptic connections, each capable of being modified to allow for growth and adaptation. Cajal studied this newly revealed phenomenon for four years, identifying as well so-called ‘dendritic spines’ – small membranous protrusions from a neuron’s input fibres that typically receive input from a single synapse. He used his artistic skills to make meticulous drawings and then published his findings in his magnum opus Revista Trimestral de Histología Normal y Patológica, which had an impact on the scientific community similar to Darwin’s breakthrough On the Origin of Species.

By providing the most accurate description of the neuron’s function and mechanism, it changed the way neuroscience worked and cleared the path for the formulation of neuron doctrine proposed by German anatomist Heinrich von Waldeyer-Hartz. Cajal was a prodigious publisher and contributor to medical journals. He was greatly feted and heaped with awards, including the 1906 Nobel Prize for Physiology or Medicine, which he shared with Golgi. Cajal also found time to work in other areas of medicine, notably cancer, and to set up his own research institute in Madrid. For all the breadth of his achievements, he will always be best remembered for disentangling the neuron from its imagined network."


(Seth, Anil, ed. 30-Second Brain. London: Icon Books, 2017. p. 23)
Location: Germany
By Atla
#331884
Consul wrote: June 5th, 2019, 1:17 pmBy which definition?
I mean standard philosophical materialism which sees matter as fundamental.
By far, the most plausible and most defensible assumption is that the brain is the organ of consciousness, and that the field/stream or state of consciousness with its experiential contents is constituted or realized by and in the brain through extremely complex neurological mechanisms.

"The human brain is the most complex entity we know of. It contains at least 90 billion neurons (nerve cells). Each of these is a complex information-processing device in its own right and interacts with about 1,000 other neurons. Understanding this degree of complexity is a daunting task."

(Seth, Anil, ed. 30-Second Brain. London: Icon Books, 2017. p. 6)

As I already said, the neuroscience of consciousness is a new, 21st-century science that is still in its infancy. There couldn't have been such a science before Santiago Ramón y Cajal's revolutionary discoveries at the end of the 19th century:

"Acknowledged by many to be the architect of modern neurobiology, as a young man Cajal tried very hard to keep out of medicine altogether. He wanted to be an artist, but his father (a professor of dissection) was equally adamant that he should be a doctor. After miserable but educational apprenticeships with a cobbler and a barber, Cajal gained his medical licence and buckled down to join the family business, eventually being appointed Professor of Anatomy at Valencia.

He kept up with his drawing, making many anatomical studies, and it is possible that it was his artistic eye that led him to his greatest discovery. When in 1887, now at the University of Barcelona, he looked at the Italian physician Camillo Golgi’s immaculately stained slides of brain cells, he saw what others had not. Until this time, the prevailing orthodoxy was that the nervous system was a single reticular (mesh-like) construct without discrete cellular components (neurons). Cajal realized however that what Golgi’s images clearly showed was that the nervous system was a network of discrete cellular components. This was a correct interpretation that crucially allowed neurons to be regarded as the functional „units of the brain – free agents that could form many synaptic connections, each capable of being modified to allow for growth and adaptation. Cajal studied this newly revealed phenomenon for four years, identifying as well so-called ‘dendritic spines’ – small membranous protrusions from a neuron’s input fibres that typically receive input from a single synapse. He used his artistic skills to make meticulous drawings and then published his findings in his magnum opus Revista Trimestral de Histología Normal y Patológica, which had an impact on the scientific community similar to Darwin’s breakthrough On the Origin of Species.

By providing the most accurate description of the neuron’s function and mechanism, it changed the way neuroscience worked and cleared the path for the formulation of neuron doctrine proposed by German anatomist Heinrich von Waldeyer-Hartz. Cajal was a prodigious publisher and contributor to medical journals. He was greatly feted and heaped with awards, including the 1906 Nobel Prize for Physiology or Medicine, which he shared with Golgi. Cajal also found time to work in other areas of medicine, notably cancer, and to set up his own research institute in Madrid. For all the breadth of his achievements, he will always be best remembered for disentangling the neuron from its imagined network."

(Seth, Anil, ed. 30-Second Brain. London: Icon Books, 2017. p. 23)
Also wishful thinking. You pulled the complexity card, but again there is no known reason why complexity would anything have to do with matter acquiring qualia.

Neuroscience of consciousness isn't all that new, as I said we have by now mapped the inner mechanisms of the human brain/mind to a remarkable detail. The last 100 years were really fruitful, and despite that, nothing about matter acquiring qualia was found.

And saying that there is something going on in the brain that can't be going on in the rest of the universe contradicts the known laws of physics.

You say that the above is by far the most plausible and defensible assumption, I'd say it's supported by no evidence at all and contradicts physics.
User avatar
By Consul
#331885
Atla wrote: June 5th, 2019, 1:35 pm
Consul wrote: June 5th, 2019, 1:17 pmBy which definition?
I mean standard philosophical materialism which sees matter as fundamental.
No definition of materialism/physicalism I know renders a neurophysiological explanation of mind/consciousness impossible by definition.
Atla wrote: June 5th, 2019, 1:35 pm
Consul wrote: June 5th, 2019, 1:17 pmBy far, the most plausible and most defensible assumption is that the brain is the organ of consciousness, and that the field/stream or state of consciousness with its experiential contents is constituted or realized by and in the brain through extremely complex neurological mechanisms.
Also wishful thinking. You pulled the complexity card, but again there is no known reason why complexity would anything have to do with matter acquiring qualia.
Neuroscience of consciousness isn't all that new, as I said we have by now mapped the inner mechanisms of the human brain/mind to a remarkable detail. The last 100 years were really fruitful, and despite that, nothing about matter acquiring qualia was found.
And saying that there is something going on in the brain that can't be going on in the rest of the universe contradicts the known laws of physics
Rubbish! Mind and consciousness depend upon physical systems with the right degree and the right sort of (structural, functional, and informational) complexity, and animal brains (integrated into animal organisms) are the only (natural) physical systems in the cosmos that have the requisite degree and sort of complexity.

What makes the antimaterialistic soul theory absurd is that it ascribes complex minds/consciousnesses to the simplest things, viz. zero-dimensional "soul-points", whose degree of structural and functional complexity is zero.

According to neuroreductive materialism, qualia are a special kind (the phenomenal one) of complex or structural physical properties of neural networks in the CNS.
Atla wrote: June 5th, 2019, 1:35 pmYou say that the above is by far the most plausible and defensible assumption, I'd say it's supported by no evidence at all and contradicts physics.
No, it doesn't, and it is supported by ample scientific evidence (especially coming from medicine, anaesthesiology, psychopathology).
What's your alternative theory that you think is more strongly supported by evidence than the brain theory? Panpsychism?
Location: Germany
User avatar
By Felix
#331886
Tamminen: "It seems that with the concept of 'noumenon' Kant suggested the possibility of genuine transcendence."

Kant rejected the idea that there is nothing in the mind that does not derive from sense experience, and suggested there are transcendental forms of intuition.

Tamminen: "But as I said, I think that the only rational concept of transcendence is transcendence in relation to immanence, subjectivity: transcendence of knowing, not transcendence of being."

I don't see how you could have genuine transcendence of knowing without some degree of transcendence of being. If all of your knowledge comes from sensory experience and your thoughts about it, you are stuck in that mental hamster-wheel. A change in being/consciousness is necessary to even recognize you are in that trap and escape from it, and this requires suprarational rather than rational insight.
User avatar
By Sculptor1
#331887
Atla wrote: June 4th, 2019, 2:37 pm Easy. The rock is made of mindstuff or whatever, and your head is also made of mindstuff or whatever, I throw the rock at you and your skull splits open.

Anyway you have accused me of believing in ghosts, of disregarding science, believing that nothing exists, being a solipsist. You are ridiculous.
Lotta whatever.
A rock is matter. That is definitive.
Get over it.
By Tamminen
#331893
In fact this is very simple. When you look around, you do not find your looking in the space you are looking in. This is true of physical space, but also logical space. Therefore it is impossible to reduce consciousness to its material objects. Remember that also brains are material objects.

You can see your eye, but not your looking.
By Tamminen
#331895
Felix wrote: June 5th, 2019, 5:43 pm Tamminen: "It seems that with the concept of 'noumenon' Kant suggested the possibility of genuine transcendence."

Kant rejected the idea that there is nothing in the mind that does not derive from sense experience, and suggested there are transcendental forms of intuition.
Right. And then there is something else we can only speculate about: the noumena. But that was Kant.
Tamminen: "But as I said, I think that the only rational concept of transcendence is transcendence in relation to immanence, subjectivity: transcendence of knowing, not transcendence of being."

I don't see how you could have genuine transcendence of knowing without some degree of transcendence of being.
Suppose there is something that no one can be in contact with, physically, or know anything about it. It is still there, and its being depends on our being, or to be precise, the being of the subject. Materialism does not accept this view.
If all of your knowledge comes from sensory experience and your thoughts about it, you are stuck in that mental hamster-wheel. A change in being/consciousness is necessary to even recognize you are in that trap and escape from it, and this requires suprarational rather than rational insight.
It is an interesting question whether rationality is spontaneous or given to us. I have thought that it comes from our existential situation that is "given" in the sense that we just find ourselves in the middle of it. But on the other hand, we accept this "given" rationality as our own, so that what was a "foreign land" becomes our home. The world reveals itself to us, and loses its transcendence. It becomes our community of existence. But we need no suprarationality, in my opinion, although I do not know what exactly you mean by it.
  • 1
  • 12
  • 13
  • 14
  • 15
  • 16
  • 37

Current Philosophy Book of the Month

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

2025 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Riddle of Alchemy

The Riddle of Alchemy
by Paul Kiritsis
January 2025

They Love You Until You Start Thinking For Yourself

They Love You Until You Start Thinking For Yourself
by Monica Omorodion Swaida
February 2025

2024 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...

The Advent of Time: A Solution to the Problem of Evil...
by Indignus Servus
November 2024

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age

Reconceptualizing Mental Illness in the Digital Age
by Elliott B. Martin, Jr.
October 2024

Zen and the Art of Writing

Zen and the Art of Writing
by Ray Hodgson
September 2024

How is God Involved in Evolution?

How is God Involved in Evolution?
by Joe P. Provenzano, Ron D. Morgan, and Dan R. Provenzano
August 2024

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters

Launchpad Republic: America's Entrepreneurial Edge and Why It Matters
by Howard Wolk
July 2024

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side

Quest: Finding Freddie: Reflections from the Other Side
by Thomas Richard Spradlin
June 2024

Neither Safe Nor Effective

Neither Safe Nor Effective
by Dr. Colleen Huber
May 2024

Now or Never

Now or Never
by Mary Wasche
April 2024

Meditations

Meditations
by Marcus Aurelius
March 2024

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes

Beyond the Golden Door: Seeing the American Dream Through an Immigrant's Eyes
by Ali Master
February 2024

The In-Between: Life in the Micro

The In-Between: Life in the Micro
by Christian Espinosa
January 2024

2023 Philosophy Books of the Month

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise

Entanglement - Quantum and Otherwise
by John K Danenbarger
January 2023

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul

Mark Victor Hansen, Relentless: Wisdom Behind the Incomparable Chicken Soup for the Soul
by Mitzi Perdue
February 2023

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness

Rediscovering the Wisdom of Human Nature: How Civilization Destroys Happiness
by Chet Shupe
March 2023

The Unfakeable Code®

The Unfakeable Code®
by Tony Jeton Selimi
April 2023

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are

The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are
by Alan Watts
May 2023

Killing Abel

Killing Abel
by Michael Tieman
June 2023

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead

Reconfigurement: Reconfiguring Your Life at Any Stage and Planning Ahead
by E. Alan Fleischauer
July 2023

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough

First Survivor: The Impossible Childhood Cancer Breakthrough
by Mark Unger
August 2023

Predictably Irrational

Predictably Irrational
by Dan Ariely
September 2023

Artwords

Artwords
by Beatriz M. Robles
November 2023

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope

Fireproof Happiness: Extinguishing Anxiety & Igniting Hope
by Dr. Randy Ross
December 2023

2022 Philosophy Books of the Month

Emotional Intelligence At Work

Emotional Intelligence At Work
by Richard M Contino & Penelope J Holt
January 2022

Free Will, Do You Have It?

Free Will, Do You Have It?
by Albertus Kral
February 2022

My Enemy in Vietnam

My Enemy in Vietnam
by Billy Springer
March 2022

2X2 on the Ark

2X2 on the Ark
by Mary J Giuffra, PhD
April 2022

The Maestro Monologue

The Maestro Monologue
by Rob White
May 2022

What Makes America Great

What Makes America Great
by Bob Dowell
June 2022

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!

The Truth Is Beyond Belief!
by Jerry Durr
July 2022

Living in Color

Living in Color
by Mike Murphy
August 2022 (tentative)

The Not So Great American Novel

The Not So Great American Novel
by James E Doucette
September 2022

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches

Mary Jane Whiteley Coggeshall, Hicksite Quaker, Iowa/National Suffragette And Her Speeches
by John N. (Jake) Ferris
October 2022

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All

In It Together: The Beautiful Struggle Uniting Us All
by Eckhart Aurelius Hughes
November 2022

The Smartest Person in the Room: The Root Cause and New Solution for Cybersecurity

The Smartest Person in the Room
by Christian Espinosa
December 2022

2021 Philosophy Books of the Month

The Biblical Clock: The Untold Secrets Linking the Universe and Humanity with God's Plan

The Biblical Clock
by Daniel Friedmann
March 2021

Wilderness Cry: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach to Understanding God and the Universe

Wilderness Cry
by Dr. Hilary L Hunt M.D.
April 2021

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute: Tools To Spark Your Dream And Ignite Your Follow-Through

Fear Not, Dream Big, & Execute
by Jeff Meyer
May 2021

Surviving the Business of Healthcare: Knowledge is Power

Surviving the Business of Healthcare
by Barbara Galutia Regis M.S. PA-C
June 2021

Winning the War on Cancer: The Epic Journey Towards a Natural Cure

Winning the War on Cancer
by Sylvie Beljanski
July 2021

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream

Defining Moments of a Free Man from a Black Stream
by Dr Frank L Douglas
August 2021

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts

If Life Stinks, Get Your Head Outta Your Buts
by Mark L. Wdowiak
September 2021

The Preppers Medical Handbook

The Preppers Medical Handbook
by Dr. William W Forgey M.D.
October 2021

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress: A Practical Guide

Natural Relief for Anxiety and Stress
by Dr. Gustavo Kinrys, MD
November 2021

Dream For Peace: An Ambassador Memoir

Dream For Peace
by Dr. Ghoulem Berrah
December 2021


All sensations ,pain, perceptions of all kin[…]

Censorship of "misinformation"

Misinformation is not the problem, citizen gulli[…]

Is Bullying Part of Human Adaptation?

Yes, bullying is sociopathic as it occurs in vio[…]

Materialism Vs Idealism

Yes, but to what philosophical end? Where does I[…]